Podchaser Logo
Home
Does a porpoise have a purpose? Agency and goals in evolution (Ep 115)

Does a porpoise have a purpose? Agency and goals in evolution (Ep 115)

Released Thursday, 8th February 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Does a porpoise have a purpose? Agency and goals in evolution (Ep 115)

Does a porpoise have a purpose? Agency and goals in evolution (Ep 115)

Does a porpoise have a purpose? Agency and goals in evolution (Ep 115)

Does a porpoise have a purpose? Agency and goals in evolution (Ep 115)

Thursday, 8th February 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Rate Episode

Episode Transcript

Transcripts are displayed as originally observed. Some content, including advertisements may have changed.

Use Ctrl + F to search

0:00

Hey, Big Biology listeners! A reminder that we're

0:02

moving into a more intensive period of fundraising

0:04

over the next few months, so you'll notice

0:06

a couple of changes to our show. First,

0:08

if you listen to us on Spotify, you'll

0:11

now hear two or three short ad breaks

0:13

during the hour. Remember, we're a non-profit entity,

0:15

and we don't want to insert commercials into

0:18

the show, but to keep it going, we

0:20

have to use all options. Second,

0:22

if you're a regular listener of Big

0:24

Biology, consider donating through our website, or

0:26

even better, sign up to be a

0:28

patron by making a monthly donation

0:31

through Patreon. If enough listeners donate the

0:33

equivalent of what an espresso or two

0:35

costs per month, you can help us

0:37

have stable funding that will keep the

0:39

show going well into the future. And

0:41

remember, Art, Cam, and I donate our

0:44

time. But producer Molly, interns Dana and

0:46

Keating, and our webmaster Steve, they

0:48

all depend on your support. Great.

0:51

So either go to

0:53

our website, www.bigbiology.org, and

0:55

make a donation, or

0:57

go to patreon.com/bigbio and become a patron

0:59

for just a few dollars a month.

1:02

Patrons also get cool insider stuff, like

1:05

access to behind-the-scenes audio from our guests

1:07

about their lives, their hobbies, and their

1:09

careers. Now, on to the show. Marty

1:22

and Art, it's good to see you

1:25

two philosophers today. Philosophers? Norwegian

1:27

Winter got you confused, Cam.

1:29

We're biologists. Wait, but PhD

1:32

stands for Doctor of Philosophy.

1:35

Technically, Cam's right. We are philosophers

1:37

in the sense that all sciences

1:39

are rooted historically in philosophy, and

1:42

that meant the pursuit of wisdom,

1:44

scholarship, and expertise. Fail. But

1:47

there is a discipline where the

1:49

two meet. The philosophy of biology

1:51

explores fundamental topics like how the

1:53

meaning of terms and critical assessments

1:55

of assumptions have changed through time.

1:57

And if you're a regular big biology listener, you

2:00

probably heard past episodes with philosophers

2:02

of biology like Dan Nicholson, Dennis

2:04

Walsh, and many others. I

2:06

think most practicing biologists, myself included, rarely

2:08

read the philosophy of biology literature, but

2:11

those are some of my favorite episodes

2:13

because they've made me stop and reflect

2:15

on ideas and concepts that I often

2:17

use but never really thought deeply about

2:20

their meanings. In a 2019

2:22

article in the Proceedings of the National

2:24

Academy of Sciences, Lucy Laplan and colleagues

2:26

argued that philosophy plays a critical role

2:28

in the sciences. An example they highlight

2:30

is a critique of the cell versus

2:33

non-self idea in immunology. Philosophers pointed out

2:35

that the idea of self breaks down

2:37

will be recognized that all organisms are

2:39

made up of communities of non-self symbionts

2:42

and the shift has real-life implications

2:44

for developing medical treatments. Thank you

2:46

philosophers. One active area

2:48

in the philosophy of biology is

2:50

evolution by natural selection. Concepts

2:53

like fitness, selection, adaptation, contingency,

2:55

and determinism pop up all

2:58

the time. But talk

3:00

to philosophers of biology and you find out that

3:02

their meanings are far less clear than you would

3:04

think. For example, think about the

3:06

phrase survival of the fittest. When

3:09

we define fitness as the ability to

3:11

survive and reproduce, the phrase becomes tautological

3:13

because we're saying essentially survival of those

3:16

who survive. This is why the philosopher

3:18

Eliot Sober has said we need a

3:20

better definition of fitness. Another topic we've

3:22

covered a lot recently on the show

3:24

and that also shows up in a

3:27

lot of philosophical analyses is

3:29

agency. Agency has been

3:31

defined very differently inside and outside of

3:33

biology. Agency also carries a lot of

3:36

baggage which puts a lot of biologists

3:38

on edge. When you say

3:40

that organisms have purposes and goals, it

3:43

opens the door to conscious intention

3:45

and even supernatural effects and forces.

3:47

Yet even if we recognize that

3:49

most of what organisms do to

3:51

survive and reproduce is done unconsciously,

3:53

we often use casual and

3:56

sometimes clumsy language. Think about the cuckoo,

3:58

a bird that lays eggs in

4:00

the nest of other species. The cuckoo egg

4:02

typically hatches first, and the cuckoo chick then

4:04

pushes the host eggs out of the nest.

4:07

We might casually say that the cuckoo chick

4:09

does this because it consciously wants all the

4:11

food for itself. We often use

4:13

this kind of language as shorthand to help

4:15

us explain why the chick behaves the way

4:17

it does, even though it

4:19

may not be making a conscious choice.

4:22

A more traditional explanation would say that

4:24

this behavior evolved by natural selection acting

4:26

on heritable variation in the context of

4:28

an evolutionary arms race with its host.

4:31

So, while there is a growing interest

4:33

in the notion of agency in evolutionary

4:35

biology, there's still a lot of confusion

4:37

and debate, even among us, about what

4:39

it means, as well as its relationship

4:41

to fitness, selection, and adaptation.

4:44

Our guest today is Samir Akasha, who's

4:46

a professor of philosophy of science at

4:48

the University of Bristol in the UK.

4:50

His 2006 book, Evolution and the Levels

4:52

of Selection, won the Lakatos Award. Today,

4:54

we talk with Samir about his 2018

4:56

book entitled Agents and

4:59

Goals in Evolution. In contrast to

5:02

our past discussions of agency, Samir takes

5:04

a different approach. He

5:06

asks in the book, quote, Does

5:08

thinking about organisms as agents have

5:10

a genuine scientific role to play in

5:12

our understanding of adaptive evolution, or is

5:14

it simply another application of anthropomorphic

5:16

language? In our chat, we

5:18

look critically at the different definitions of

5:21

agency in biology. How is it different

5:23

from phenotypic plasticity? And do

5:25

we separate agency and fitness? And

5:27

what about agency below the organismal level?

5:29

Could a gene be considered an agent

5:31

if it acts selfishly to increase copies

5:33

of itself, like in cases of intergenomic

5:35

conflict? And what about groups

5:38

of humans or even groups of different

5:40

species that exhibit cooperative, goal-directed behavior? Do

5:43

groups have agency distinct from individual

5:45

members? Samir argues that

5:47

although we gain insight by

5:49

anthropomorphizing some adaptive traits, there's

5:51

still value in understanding how agency

5:53

influences evolution, even if we don't

5:55

know about consciousness in that organism.

5:58

We also discuss whether the process of

6:00

evolution by natural selection represents a form

6:02

of agency. This might sound odd,

6:05

but recall that Darwin himself depicted natural

6:07

selection with a language of intent, as

6:09

a background process that's always scrutinizing

6:12

populations, keeping the good and eliminating

6:14

the bad. We debate

6:16

some really difficult problems like whether agency

6:18

can evolve, is there heritable variation for

6:20

it, and how would we measure that?

6:22

Something we've been thinking about a lot,

6:25

but I'm not sure we've totally resolved.

6:27

So stay tuned for a philosophical assessment

6:29

of agents, goals, and evolution. I'm Cameron

6:31

Gallenbore. I'm Art Woods. And I'm Marty

6:33

Martin, and you're listening to BIG Biology.

6:51

Samira Kasha, thanks so much for joining us on

6:53

BIG Biology today. It's my pleasure.

6:55

We're super excited to talk to you

6:57

today about your recent book, Agents and

7:00

Goals and Evolution. Maybe to

7:02

begin, could you start off by

7:04

defining what is a

7:06

biological agent? Well, that's a

7:08

complicated and difficult matter. Let

7:11

me give you my take on it. As

7:13

I see it, the place we need to start is

7:15

by asking pretty much the question you did. I mean,

7:18

what do we mean by the term agent? And

7:20

why do people think that this is a good concept

7:22

or term to use when thinking about

7:25

biology? And I think that's an important

7:27

question to ask, because there's this flurry of

7:29

interest in the notion of

7:32

agency in biology, as many of

7:34

your past contributors have discussed, and as you'll

7:36

be aware, and as a lot of philosophers

7:38

have joined this discussion too. But

7:40

on the face of it, I mean, that's a

7:43

bit odd, because if you open any biology textbook

7:45

in any branch of biology, I

7:47

very much doubt that the term agent is going

7:49

to appear in the index. So

7:52

that basically raises the question, well, why should

7:54

this notion be so important for sort of

7:56

philosophical reflections about biology if the science itself

7:58

is a good thing? doesn't seem to have

8:00

any use for it. So that's I think the first sort

8:03

of skeptical question I would ask and next

8:05

move I would make is then to say well if

8:07

people do want to talk about this let's do the

8:10

sort of standard thing we do in philosophy of saying

8:12

well what exactly do you mean? It's

8:14

always a good question to ask. And

8:16

as I see it there are I mean there are

8:19

a number of different motions of agents at work

8:21

both in different sciences and

8:23

in vernacular English. So

8:25

in my book I distinguish between

8:27

four different notions of

8:29

age and as a sort of prelude to

8:32

the discussion. The first is

8:34

what in in traditional philosophy we

8:36

would call an intentional agent. Someone

8:38

or thing that engages in reasoning

8:40

and in thinking and in deliberating

8:42

about what to do and choose

8:45

these courses of actions because of particular

8:47

goals that they want to achieve. Where

8:50

the goal is something that's mentally represented

8:52

by the agent. So that means

8:54

that at the very least you've got to have a mind

8:57

of some sort. Now what exactly that

8:59

I mean that's clearly intended to include

9:01

humans. Whether it includes what

9:03

else it includes you know whether

9:05

it includes all vertebrates or even

9:07

some invertebrates or even possibly microbes

9:10

it could be debated. But that as I see

9:12

it is the sort of traditional philosophical notion of

9:15

agent. An agent engages not

9:17

just in behavior but in action where

9:20

action means that they're deliberately trying to

9:22

achieve the goal. And that's what

9:25

I think of as the most

9:27

restrictive notion of agent. The literal

9:29

applicability of which is the least

9:31

if you see what I mean.

9:33

But then in different sciences we

9:35

find broader notions of agents. So

9:37

for example in AI one finds

9:39

frequent reference to talk about intelligent

9:41

agents. Where that basically means

9:43

anything you could be a control system

9:45

or piece of software or a thermostat

9:47

that doesn't always do the same thing.

9:50

That does different things depending on

9:52

the circumstance that it's in. So

9:54

typically we'll sense the environment somehow

9:57

and change its behavior depending on what

9:59

it says. I mean, so implement

10:01

stimulus response conditionals. It's an

10:03

extremely inclusive notion of agents,

10:06

that of course. Similarly,

10:08

but differently, one finds in the

10:10

economics literature talk about rational agents

10:12

and a lot of talk about

10:14

the rational agent model, where

10:17

essentially that means an

10:19

agent who engages in consistent

10:21

choice, so behaves as if

10:24

they're trying to maximize some utility

10:26

function or something like that, as

10:29

whose choice behavior is

10:31

consistent, satisfies conditions such

10:34

as transitivity, things like that. Again,

10:36

that's a broad notion of agents

10:38

in that there are no psychological

10:40

requirements. I mean, any organism

10:42

that engages in choice or behavior

10:45

of any sort could satisfy

10:47

or fail to satisfy those conditions on

10:49

being a rational agent as

10:52

understood in rational choice theory

10:54

and economics. And then

10:56

the final notion of agent that I operate with,

10:59

or that some people operate with that I distinguish,

11:01

is what I have called minimal agent.

11:04

And that just means something that

11:06

does something. So an agent

11:09

in this sense is just something that does

11:11

something rather than something to

11:13

which things happen, if you like. And

11:16

how exactly you cash that out, I

11:19

think is a difficult philosophical question. But

11:22

I mean, examples can make it clear. So to

11:24

borrow one from the philosopher Fred Dretsky that I

11:26

like to use, he said, look,

11:28

contrast these two things. A rat

11:30

moves its paw in

11:33

order to press a lever to get a pellet

11:35

of food. And an

11:38

experimental scientist puts the hand into the

11:40

cage and forcibly moves the rat's paw.

11:43

In the first case, the rat moved its

11:45

paw. In the second case, its paw was

11:47

moved. And

11:49

that he says illustrates the difference between

11:52

doing something and having something happen to

11:54

one. Sort of active versus passive. Yeah,

11:57

exactly. And then

11:59

obviously... the next thing to say about that is, well,

12:01

what, how do we cash that out precisely? What does that

12:03

really mean? And some philosophers have

12:05

thought that the answer simply lies in the

12:08

question of whether the cause was internal to

12:10

the agent or not. You

12:13

know, so if a bird flies, then

12:15

that's one thing, a hurricane, force, wind

12:18

blows the bird. That's another thing. In

12:20

one case, the cause of the, the

12:22

motor output is internal. In the second

12:24

case, there's an external cause. So

12:27

that, that's what I call the most minimal notion of

12:29

agents entirely. So those

12:31

are the four notions I operate

12:33

within some sort of rough hierarchy,

12:35

the most demanding, the intentional agent,

12:37

the least demanding, the minimal agent,

12:39

and then the intelligent agent and

12:42

the rational agent somewhere in between

12:44

those two extremes. And

12:46

then the next question to ask is,

12:48

well, which event, if any of those

12:50

notions applies to biological systems, to

12:53

which biological systems do they apply and

12:55

how do we know and why? But here

12:58

a complication comes in because I maintain, and

13:00

this is my, I guess my real interest

13:02

in my book, the much

13:04

talk of agency in the

13:06

biological realm is metaphorical rather

13:08

than literal. Particularly

13:10

in evolutionary thinking, I

13:13

claim that there's a lot of appeal

13:16

to the intentional notion of agent, the

13:18

most demanding of all, that

13:20

I think of as in many ways, the core notion,

13:23

where the agent must have a mental representation of

13:25

the goal. But the concept

13:27

is only applied metaphorically. When we say

13:29

things like the bacterium swims up an

13:31

oxygen gradient, because it wants to get to

13:33

an area of higher oxygen concentration or something like that. Yeah.

13:37

So let's, let's unpack that first one a little

13:39

bit, because I had a question lined up about

13:41

that very thing. So, you know, in the, in

13:43

the book, you make it clear that for this

13:45

more restrictive idea of agency, that it requires a

13:49

mind and a mental representation.

13:51

And at least like among

13:53

those of us, the hosts that are talking

13:56

about agency, Marty and I have sort of kicked this

13:58

back and forth. I think our concern of

14:00

agency is a little bit broader

14:02

and it encompasses basically any complex

14:04

system that's able to receive

14:07

information, process it in some way,

14:09

and make a decision. And that

14:12

doesn't invoke anything about nervous

14:14

systems or minds or mental representations. You

14:16

certainly could have biochemical networks that are

14:18

making decisions. You could make, you know,

14:21

have sort of genetic regulatory networks that

14:23

are making decisions. And so I think

14:25

that that immediately expands this

14:27

idea of agency down to very

14:30

simple organisms like an, you know, an E.

14:32

coli deciding whether or not to make the

14:34

machinery to metabolize lactose or

14:36

not. So in your conception, why do you

14:38

have to have a brain and a mental

14:40

map? Well, I don't say that

14:43

you do. I only say that

14:45

you do in order to be a

14:47

literal agent in one sense of the

14:49

term agent. But I entirely hear your

14:51

line of argument. And I think it's

14:53

one I'm sympathetic to that says, look,

14:56

there are, you know, other, so what

14:58

you might call hallmarks of agency are

15:00

found in pretty much all complex

15:02

systems, biological and maybe

15:04

even non-biological, certainly including

15:07

cells and possibly subcellular

15:09

constituents and molecular

15:11

pathways and things too. However,

15:14

I would say that that involves a somewhat

15:16

different notion of agents. So

15:18

I would actually say that's closer to the

15:21

intelligent agent notion of AI. So

15:23

basically, what we mean is that

15:25

we've got something that receives

15:28

information from the environment

15:30

and modifies its behavior

15:33

as a consequence. So in short, it doesn't always

15:35

do the same thing. What it does depends on,

15:37

on circumstance, if

15:40

you like. But then I mean, then

15:42

if that's right, then it raises the

15:44

question, do we just mean behavioral plasticity?

15:47

When we talk about agency in that sense? Exactly

15:50

what I wanted to ask. Is

15:53

this a continuous grade from intelligent

15:55

to intentional? I mean,

15:57

and is there some way to find a clear

16:00

demarcation between these kinds of

16:02

things? Well, presumably, I mean,

16:04

the intentional one is

16:07

a relatively late arrive on the

16:09

evolutionary scene. In that,

16:11

you know, however widely we think the

16:14

true intentional agency is found in

16:17

the animal world, and, you know, cognitive pathologists

16:20

have, you know, often debated, for

16:22

example, whether corvids are capable of genuine

16:25

intentional behavior or not, and opinions divide on

16:27

that issue. But what's very, very clear is

16:30

that, well, I would

16:32

say at least the vast majority of

16:34

organisms, including all invertebrates, are

16:36

not literally intentional agents. I mean, if we,

16:38

we might describe them as if they were,

16:40

when we say, you know, if the cell

16:42

wants to achieve such and such an end,

16:44

but that's, to deliberately

16:46

anthropomorphize, and maybe for good reason,

16:49

but it's not literally true. It's a

16:51

bit like saying the suitcase doesn't want to close, you

16:53

know, it might be useful thing to say, it's not

16:55

literally true. Right. What do you think

16:58

Lars Chitka might say about that? I'm not sure

17:00

if you're familiar with his work, but we spoke

17:02

to him quite a while ago. So

17:04

he's very interested in insect cognition. And

17:06

he's done really amazing work on all

17:08

sorts of bees in terms of their

17:11

capacity for solving puzzles. One

17:13

of the really neat stories that he tells is,

17:15

you know, how do bees decide,

17:17

decide to

17:19

build the nest that they do, and

17:22

the configurations that they can take, you know,

17:24

it's not like it's a sort of hardwired

17:26

always the same kind of

17:28

nest, it's very responsive to

17:31

the conditions of the environment. And he's

17:33

done incredibly sophisticated experiments to show the

17:36

amazingly elaborate kinds of outcomes from, you

17:38

know, presumably a simple cognitive

17:40

system. Yeah, no,

17:42

I mean, I think it's a genuine challenge

17:44

that I mean, at some level, it's got

17:46

to be an empirical question, I think. One

17:49

way to look at it would be to say,

17:51

well, what's to be gained, this is a formulation

17:53

inspired by Daniel Dennett, where he says something

17:56

like, heuristically, what would we gain, if

17:58

anything, by treating some

18:01

organism or collection of organisms in

18:04

the B case perhaps as an

18:06

intentional agent as if it really was trying

18:08

to achieve some goal and had

18:11

beliefs about the world and processing

18:13

information and so on. I

18:15

mean is that a useful perspective or not?

18:17

I mean the answer might very well be

18:19

yes in that sort of example but I

18:21

take it that there are examples where it

18:24

would not where we have a

18:26

purely mechanistic understanding of

18:28

the movement of some microbe

18:31

or something like that or the

18:33

growth pathway of some plant for

18:36

example. I mean it would be seem

18:38

superfluous to give a psychological explanation

18:41

of plant growth towards the

18:44

light or something then. I

18:46

mean we have a fairly

18:48

good mechanistic understanding of why the

18:51

plant responds to light

18:53

that way and if someone wanted to say well

18:56

no it's because it wants to get more sunlight

18:58

or something or wants

19:00

to grow taller than its neighbor. That would not be,

19:03

I take it scientifically useful. So one test

19:05

is just the scientific utility. Now

19:08

some philosophers and others would oppose that

19:10

methodologically by saying look the question of

19:12

whether something is useful is distinct from

19:14

the question of whether it's true and

19:16

that may be but nonetheless I

19:18

think if it isn't useful at all then

19:20

that's some indication that it's not literally true.

19:23

So as I see it I mean I wouldn't at

19:25

all insist that we know that it could only be

19:28

in vertebrates that we find

19:30

the hallmarks of true intentional agency. I

19:32

mean another point though to bear in

19:34

mind is that I mean

19:36

I started when I defined intentional agency by saying

19:39

that there really is a mental representation of the

19:41

goal. The organism really

19:43

it's not just as if it was trying

19:45

to achieve a goal it really is. But

19:48

you see if you talk instead about decision then

19:50

that's perhaps a less psychologically

19:52

demanding notion than having a

19:55

mental representation of the goal in that I

19:57

think it's perfectly sensible and plausible to say

20:00

you know, even of a developing organism that

20:02

it needs to decide which pathway to

20:04

go down. So developmental

20:07

regulatory networks can make decisions, chemical

20:10

networks can make decisions. Yeah, I mean,

20:12

you know, some people might insist that

20:15

the literal meaning of the word decision is a

20:17

conscious decision made by human. It's sort

20:20

of inherently mental. Yeah, right. Yeah, but

20:22

I don't see that. I don't see

20:24

that that's either the standard

20:26

way that the word is used in science these

20:28

days, or has anything

20:30

particular to recommend it sort

20:32

of theoretically. So I'm quite happy for

20:34

decisions to be a pretty broad thing. I'm

20:37

very happy with the idea then that, you

20:40

know, all organisms, including microbes

20:42

make decisions and maybe decisions

20:44

are made at the level

20:46

of regulatory networks and, you

20:48

know, subcellular levels too. But

20:51

if so, then I would say that

20:53

decision making and having a mental representation

20:55

of the goal come apart.

20:59

Even that the former is taxonomically widespread, the

21:01

latter isn't. So if

21:03

we can circle back a little bit

21:05

to the concept of plasticity and flexibility,

21:08

for I'd

21:10

say most practicing evolutionary

21:12

biologists, the capacity

21:15

for being

21:17

flexible and whether it's

21:19

at the level of development in response

21:22

to some environmental cues or in the

21:24

context of behavior changing, say in the

21:27

presence and absence of a predator, a

21:30

lot of those types of responses

21:32

are captured currently under the sort

21:34

of framework of phenotypic plasticity. And

21:36

so just based on your

21:39

description, it seems that being

21:41

plastic and flexible

21:44

is inherent to being

21:47

agential in your response. Yeah, I would

21:49

agree. In all of the senses of

21:52

agency, in all of the four senses

21:54

that I've operated, I've distinguished. So are

21:56

they so intertwined that they are essentially

21:59

capturing? the same phenomenon or can we

22:01

sort of decouple them from one another?

22:04

Yeah, I know. I mean, it's tricky. I

22:06

mean, I do think that, you

22:09

know, the notion of phenotypic plasticity and

22:11

behavioral plasticity, that being a subset of

22:14

phenotypic plasticity, you know, given that not

22:16

all phenotypes of behaviors, you

22:19

know, captures a lot of what people

22:21

who talk about agency are

22:23

trying to say, and probably in a

22:26

more sort of acceptable way

22:28

to many practicing scientists. And I think

22:30

that's exactly the source of some of

22:32

the opposition to the language of

22:35

agency that one finds these days

22:37

where people say, look, you're just using

22:39

this mystical-sounding term, which the

22:41

cash value of which is something that we could say

22:43

anyway. Right. Now, you see,

22:45

I think that's a valid criticism of some

22:47

projects that involve the notion of agency, but

22:50

not of mine. In

22:53

some theorists, including some of

22:55

my colleagues in philosophy of

22:57

biology, seem to have convinced

22:59

themselves that there's a deep

23:01

and interesting sense in which

23:04

some organisms or maybe all organisms

23:06

and maybe other biological entities

23:09

too, are agents. And

23:11

their task is to figure out what that sense is,

23:14

subject to the constraint that it

23:16

better be interesting, and better not

23:18

just reduce the behavioral plasticity. But

23:21

that seems to me an odd way to proceed. So

23:24

that's why I'm one of the people who's

23:26

somewhat skeptical about the notion, despite having worked

23:28

on it myself. But my project

23:30

is a somewhat different one in that

23:33

I was, in writing my books,

23:35

specifically interested in a mode

23:37

of thinking and speaking

23:40

that is peculiar to evolutionary

23:42

biology, I think, which

23:45

involves deliberately

23:47

anthropomorphizing for

23:49

the purposes of achieving evolutionary insights.

23:52

And one example of which is

23:54

that the practice of taking

23:57

the adaptive function

24:00

or rationale of some phenotype,

24:03

but particularly a behavior, but not

24:05

necessarily, in the sense that the

24:07

reason why it's evolved. And then

24:09

treating that as if it was the

24:11

organism's own goal, a

24:14

literal goal mentally represented, even when

24:16

it really isn't. And

24:18

I give many examples in my book

24:20

of this practice actually at work in

24:22

evolutionary biology, manifest by the use of

24:24

intentional language. So when we say things

24:26

like that the female rat kills its

24:28

injured young, because it knows that they

24:30

won't survive, it doesn't want to waste

24:32

resources on them, for example, there

24:35

we explicitly employ, you know,

24:37

vocabulary that has its natural home in

24:40

relation to conscious deliberate human behavior, by

24:43

way of giving an evolutionary explanation, or an

24:46

adaptive explanation of the infanticidal

24:48

behavior of the female rat.

24:51

And so that was the phenomenon I was

24:53

specifically interested in the use of intentional vocabulary

24:57

in an evolutionary context. And

25:00

so I took my project, I mean, I

25:02

approached it very much in the spirit of

25:04

a kind of anthropologist of science, you know,

25:07

my starting point was, look, there is this

25:09

pre existing practice out there in the scientific

25:11

literature, that's really unusual and

25:13

philosophically puzzling. And what

25:16

on earth could be the point of talking

25:18

that way, given that it seems to willfully

25:20

invite a confusion of proximate and ultimate? And

25:23

given that it seems to just be a

25:25

form of anthropomorphism, could it really be

25:27

doing any scientific work? That was

25:30

the question I started from. And

25:32

I think of that as a somewhat

25:34

different project, indeed, an orthogonal project, to

25:36

the one that many people, you know,

25:39

both biology and philosophy, who talk about

25:41

agency are ultimately engaged in. So

25:43

I want to push back a little bit, because you

25:46

made a great case, and this adaptationist

25:49

program has been and is pervasive in

25:52

biology. But there's this particular word that

25:54

I hear you using that I'd like

25:56

you to address, and it's mental, right?

25:59

So An important

26:01

qualifier of agency

26:03

that you write about is integration.

26:06

So it's not just the

26:09

potential to perceive the problem or to sort

26:11

of think about the problem, but then the

26:13

system does something about it. So can

26:16

you expand the definition of mental? And

26:19

more importantly, it seems to me to

26:21

be leaning on mental as

26:23

the qualification of agential and justification

26:25

of how to think about that.

26:27

That seems akin to the anthropomorphizing

26:30

and adaptationist perspective. It's a

26:32

move that allows you to

26:34

do other things, but I

26:37

don't know. I guess I'm just not on board that

26:39

mental is something special

26:42

because you have to have integration. And as Art

26:44

was saying a minute ago, there's a lot of

26:46

different systems and even elements of systems that integrate.

26:49

Yeah, no, I mean, I agree that

26:51

integration and mentality are not

26:53

exactly the same thing, certainly.

26:55

So I mean, what I'm getting

26:57

at when I use the term mental is

26:59

that just the assumption that

27:02

psychological descriptors like believes,

27:06

wants, tries, apply

27:09

literally in the human case and

27:12

quite possibly in other non-human

27:15

cases too. But

27:17

don't apply literally in all cases

27:19

where there are sort of hallmarks

27:21

of agency in the sense of

27:24

flexible behavior, plasticity,

27:26

decision making, information

27:28

integration, all of that. Now,

27:31

I mean, that move could be

27:34

contested, I agree. That's not self-evidently

27:37

true. But I think

27:39

that's the natural default assumption that this is

27:41

the home of this vocabulary. It's

27:44

really weird to my mind to think

27:46

that the psychological language of

27:49

that sort literally characterizes what an

27:51

earthworm does. I

27:53

just don't think it's true. And

27:55

that's fair, but I think that's where I'm

27:57

coming from. I mean, to just sort of…

28:00

distinguish these forms of agency using

28:02

human cognition as

28:05

sort of a frame for how we think about all

28:07

of these other things. I sort of approach it from

28:09

the other direction. Life as a

28:11

complex system, one of its manifestations ends up

28:13

being the human brain, but

28:15

even the vertebrate immune system can learn

28:17

in an exquisite way that

28:19

has nothing to do with how nerves

28:21

learn. I mean if we had a

28:23

better grasp on what consciousness was and

28:25

the interplay between consciousness and mental,

28:29

maybe I'd feel a little bit more comfortable, but because those

28:31

are such abstractions too, I don't know, it

28:33

feels like a strange place to start. Right,

28:36

I see. Yeah, I mean why

28:38

do I start in that place? You see, I

28:40

mean I entirely agree with you that, for example,

28:42

the adaptive immune system learns. Yeah,

28:45

that seems that seems absolutely clear. But

28:47

why do I start with the mental?

28:50

I mean I think it's because my

28:52

specific interest is in this anthropomorphizing tendency,

28:55

or at least in that book,

28:57

that's the thing I'm specifically interested

28:59

in, is this anthropomorphizing tendency within

29:01

evolutionary biology. And my overarching question

29:03

in that book was, look, is this tendency

29:06

to use the language of intentional

29:08

psychology in an evolutionary context

29:10

in order to cause adaptive

29:13

explanations, is there any

29:15

real good reason to do that? Or

29:18

is it just a sort of casual

29:20

anthropomorphic bias? Does it pick out some

29:23

genuine class of phenomena? Or is it,

29:25

does it really just more reflect the

29:28

fact that the investigators are humans

29:30

themselves and haven't entirely always managed

29:32

to shed themselves of their anthropomorphic

29:35

bias? But in terms

29:37

of thinking about the origins of agency

29:39

itself and the origins of intentionality

29:42

and consciousness, I mean, I

29:44

think I agree with you

29:46

that precursor forms of all

29:48

of these things are found

29:50

in a much simpler biological

29:52

systems and that somehow

29:54

or other, you know, the

29:56

evolutionary process gave rise to creatures

29:58

whose cognition was sophisticated. sophisticated enough,

30:01

for whatever reasons exactly, that

30:04

they could actually mentally represent

30:06

their goals. Yeah. So Samira,

30:08

I gathered from your book that you

30:11

sort of slot these different ideas about

30:14

sort of levels of agency into what you

30:16

call type one and type two. And

30:18

type one is about organismal agency

30:20

itself, which I think, you

30:22

know, now many biologists are starting to hear

30:24

about and having strong reactions to.

30:27

Type two is this idea

30:29

that the process of evolution

30:32

itself and natural selection can

30:34

be agential and or

30:36

that it may appear to be

30:38

agential because of the sort of

30:40

psychological and intentional language that's used.

30:43

And I would say like it feels like

30:46

your book is largely, you know, in

30:48

the end dismisses this idea that type

30:50

two agency is important and actually captures

30:52

something real that's happening in biology and

30:54

that that we're sort of, in

30:57

a sense, taken for a ride by

30:59

the language that we use to describe

31:02

type two agency. Yeah, no, that's

31:04

exactly right. So it was, yeah, my sort of

31:06

simple one line argument is that

31:08

type one good in certain cases,

31:11

scientifically justifiable, despite being

31:13

anthropomorphic, type two,

31:16

generally not good, anthropomorphic,

31:18

but bad. So type two in

31:20

at least the paradigm sort

31:22

I have in mind involves, you

31:24

know, thinking of the evolutionary process,

31:26

as you say, or the process

31:28

of natural selection as a form

31:31

of agency, if you like. And Darwin

31:33

himself was the first to do this

31:35

in a number of passages in the

31:37

origin of species, where he says natural

31:39

things like natural selection is daily and

31:42

out, he's scrutinizing the world, looking

31:44

for any advantage and preserving

31:47

what's good, eliminating what's bad. So

31:49

that is quite deliberately using this

31:52

intentional language to characterize the

31:54

process of natural selection itself.

31:57

Now, Darwin went on to say, look, these are

31:59

just metaphors, but don't worry about it. It's

32:02

not a big deal. And I think

32:04

in fact, he was cavalier on that point. Because,

32:06

I mean, one of the

32:08

things that people didn't realize in the didn't

32:10

understand in the earliest days

32:12

of post Darwin was that the

32:15

process is, of course, mechanistic and

32:17

doesn't have any foresight, there is

32:19

no goal sorts, which evolution is

32:22

striving or anything like that. And, you

32:25

know, any attempt to think otherwise

32:27

is really is to misunderstand Darwin's

32:30

achievement. But nonetheless, I do

32:32

think that sort of vestiges

32:34

of that type two form

32:36

of agential reasoning and thinking

32:39

are still alive today, in

32:41

fact, because you see, I think

32:44

that we very often treat the

32:46

simplest sort of natural selection as

32:48

if it was paradigmatic. And

32:51

so by I mean, the simplest sort of natural

32:53

selection is just one we've got a number of

32:55

variants in a population in a fixed environment, with

32:58

no frequency dependence. And

33:01

the evolutionary process when driven by

33:03

natural selection simply involves fixation of

33:05

the best variant and elimination of

33:08

the worst ones and the, you

33:10

know, monotonic increase of mean

33:13

population fitness until it reaches

33:15

a maximum so pushes the

33:17

population up the adaptive landscape, all

33:20

ideas that are, you know, have their place.

33:22

And are useful, but rest on, you know,

33:24

that's only the very simplest case. And,

33:26

you know, it's all the evolutionists know,

33:29

those things hold true under restrictive model

33:31

assumptions that almost never apply. And in

33:34

the real world. And so I think

33:36

the tendency to adopt that

33:38

language leads us to

33:40

think that the simplest form of

33:42

natural selection as a sort of

33:45

simple optimization process is

33:47

the paradigm example. And

33:49

obviously people who really know the science

33:51

know that that isn't true. But

33:54

nonetheless, I think a vast number of

33:56

people who sort of know a bit about evolution and

33:58

natural selection, don't understand. understand that that

34:00

isn't true. And the use

34:02

of this intentional language, thinking of

34:05

the evolutionary processes, you

34:07

know, either driven to achieve some

34:09

goal or in any case as directed

34:12

in some sort of way or as pushing

34:15

populations up landscapes by the steepest

34:17

path, that sort of thing. Those

34:20

mistaken notions go hand in hand, I

34:22

think, with the use of these

34:25

anthropomorphic intentional descriptors to characterize the

34:27

process of evolution by natural selection.

34:29

So that's why I say type

34:31

too bad. But I want

34:33

to say type one, which involves

34:35

thinking of an actual evolved entity,

34:38

typically an organism, but possibly a

34:40

group or maybe even a gene

34:43

as akin to an agent, and

34:45

as trying to achieve a goal can

34:47

be in certain cases, a

34:50

useful mode of description.

34:52

I try and make this argument

34:54

that although anthropomorphic, it does genuine

34:56

work in that it picks out

34:58

a real phenomenon that, you

35:00

know, certainly could be described otherwise, but that

35:03

there is a real reason to describe this

35:05

way. And that's when I start

35:07

talking about integration and

35:09

absence of internal conflict as

35:12

being a prerequisite for thinking of

35:14

an organism as agent

35:16

like. Hey

35:24

there! Did you know Kroger always gives

35:26

you savings And

35:30

when you download the Kroger Ap, you'll enjoy

35:32

over five hundred dollars in savings every week

35:34

with digital coupons. And don't forget few points

35:36

to help you save up to one dollar

35:38

per gallon at the pump. Wanna. Save

35:40

even more with a boost membership you'll

35:42

get double few points and free delivery.

36:01

Yeah, so this is a good place to

36:03

really just ask the question, are genes

36:06

agents? Especially in

36:08

the context of thinking about transposable

36:11

elements and gene

36:13

for altruism or other

36:16

kinds of inter-genomic conflict, it

36:18

seems like our language

36:21

that we would use and our

36:23

theory to describe why there would

36:25

be selection for or against the

36:27

spread of a gene within a

36:29

genome fits within this concept

36:31

of an agent. Yeah, no, I

36:33

agree with that. And I think, I mean,

36:35

the broad story I'm trying to tell about

36:37

agency and the circumstances in which it's a

36:40

valid concept or useful concept

36:42

at least to employ in an

36:44

evolutionary context includes the

36:47

famous selfish gene notion of

36:49

Dawkins. Although I do

36:51

think of the many different sort

36:54

of lines of rationales and lines of

36:56

reasoning that Dawkins used

36:58

to support the selfish gene notion, the

37:01

one that I'm interested in is the one you

37:03

allude to, that is where

37:05

there's inter-genomic conflict, that it

37:08

makes most sense to think of a gene

37:10

as trying to achieve an outcome by

37:12

means of doing something that in this case

37:15

harms other genes within the same

37:17

genome. By now, a familiar

37:20

point and one that I think

37:22

Dawkins himself made in his

37:24

later work that the sense in which the

37:26

gene is the unit of selection where

37:29

there's inter-genomic conflict is really rather different from

37:31

the sense in which the gene is always

37:33

the unit of selection. I mean,

37:35

the latter is true in a sense,

37:38

but it's in a different sense that

37:40

we talk about genes as

37:43

the entity is being selected where

37:45

there's conflict within a single genome.

37:48

So I sometimes capture that by contrasting

37:50

the process of gene level

37:53

selection with a genetic

37:55

perspective on selection process that take

37:57

place at a different level. So,

38:00

Mir, can I ask you to tie back

38:02

genes as agents to your four types

38:05

of agents that we started with? Into

38:07

which category would genes fit for you?

38:10

Well, I would say really,

38:12

literally speaking, none of

38:14

them, because, I mean, you know, DNA is a

38:17

pretty inert molecule. I mean, obviously,

38:19

the more we know about how genes

38:21

work and, you know, how gene expression

38:24

works, you know, the more the

38:26

situation is a little bit complicated. But

38:28

I would still say that if we're

38:30

asking which of those agent concepts literally

38:33

characterise genes, I would be inclined to

38:35

say none. But nonetheless,

38:38

it can be useful to use one

38:40

or more of those concepts metaphorically

38:42

to describe genes for

38:45

certain projects. And I

38:47

think that, you know, what Dawkins and

38:50

Dennett and fellow travellers are doing is

38:52

basically taking one of those notions of

38:54

agency, namely the intentional agency one, and

38:57

using that notion, applying

38:59

that notion to genes, but in

39:01

an overtly, self consciously

39:03

metaphorical sense. I've always

39:05

been puzzled why people are so horrified by that.

39:08

I think it makes extremely good

39:10

sense to me. So long

39:12

as it's used carefully. Yeah, it's funny, I

39:15

feel relatively comfortable with, you know, the idea

39:17

of genes as a level of selection.

39:21

It's hard for me to conceive, and you

39:23

sort of said this, but it's hard for

39:25

me to conceive of genes as agents, because,

39:28

you know, to me, agency itself comes from

39:30

networks, doing computations and

39:33

making decisions. And of course, genes

39:35

don't contain those networks, right? They

39:37

can be a component of another network.

39:41

But they're just a part that is

39:44

participating in a greater whole that maybe

39:46

has agency, but that don't

39:49

have agency themselves. What do you think of that? Yeah,

39:51

I mean, I think I would agree. But

39:54

again, that's because you're using the terms

39:56

in this literal way. I mean,

39:58

I think that what say that

40:00

genes don't have themselves any

40:02

of the characteristic hallmarks of

40:05

agency, I think is true, but

40:07

I also think that that's compatible

40:10

with heuristically treating them as if

40:12

they did in order to further

40:14

our understanding of the evolutionary

40:16

processes, of certain evolutionary processes.

40:20

And so, I mean, if you

40:22

think of how people struggle to

40:24

understand the phenomenon of intra-genomic conflict

40:26

before they have the selfish gene

40:28

paradigm, which was really invented

40:30

for other reasons, really. Dawkins was

40:33

originally thinking about things like altruistic behavior

40:35

and so on. But, I

40:37

mean, I think, once you

40:39

have that idea, then

40:41

you can immediately see how to

40:43

make sense of this otherwise extremely

40:46

puzzling phenomenon. I think it'd be

40:48

useful to to give an example of

40:50

this type of inter-genomic conflict. Is there a

40:53

particular one that you really like? No

40:55

particular one. I mean, there are thousands

40:58

of these examples, but say, for

41:00

example, the phenomenon of cytoplasmic male

41:02

sterility in flowering plants,

41:05

where you have a gene within

41:07

a mitochondrion that causes

41:10

its plants to cease making

41:13

pollen, which is a really odd

41:15

thing to do. You know, the

41:17

plant, in some cases, the plant actually grows

41:19

stamen, so all

41:21

intents and balances in order to make

41:23

pollen, but then those

41:25

mitochondrial genes frustrate the

41:29

stamen from actually doing the thing that they're meant to do.

41:32

I mean, that's from the phenotypic perspective of the

41:34

whole organism. You look at them, what on earth

41:36

is that about? What's the

41:38

rationale for that? Is this an

41:40

exception to the theory of evolution or

41:42

something like that? How could it be?

41:45

But it makes perfect sense when you

41:47

realize that the mitochondrial genes are only

41:49

transmitted, but only down the

41:51

female line, so investing in pollen is a waste.

41:53

Now, that's the sort of case I have

41:56

in mind, where I say that there's a threat to the

41:58

idea that the whole organism is a waste of pollen. is

42:00

agent like because it

42:02

doesn't have if you like the

42:04

sort of phenotypic integration the behavioral

42:07

integration that one would

42:09

need in order to apply

42:11

the psychological language metaphorically

42:13

to it. So what

42:15

is it that the plant is trying to achieve? You

42:18

know is it trying to self fertilize

42:20

or not? Well on the

42:22

one hand yes because you know a lot of its

42:24

apparatus is geared to that but on the

42:26

other hand no because they don't make any problems. Yeah

42:29

and this this might be a bizarre thing to

42:31

say Samir to the author of a book on

42:33

levels of selection but you know those

42:35

kinds of arguments in the way you make

42:37

a completely fantastic case and there's no question

42:39

that these conflicts are true but

42:42

because biology is organized across

42:44

levels to sort of use

42:46

these as ways to understand

42:48

organisms you know is

42:50

it possible that these are great examples of genes

42:53

as parasites or something

42:55

different and the rest are a large

42:57

fraction of the genome and all its

42:59

regulatory components they aren't so

43:01

much parasites as commensals or mutualists I mean

43:04

you know to use the parasitic

43:06

argument to be foundational for everything

43:09

organismal I have always viewed that as an overreach.

43:11

Yeah I see I mean I think I

43:14

think I'm on board with the idea that

43:17

we can have genomic parasites and

43:19

that that actually accurately captures quite

43:22

a lot of cases of intragenomic conflict so

43:24

what's the thing that you think is overreach?

43:27

You know your arguments about why not

43:29

make pollen I mean that's sort of framed

43:32

in an adaptive context at the

43:34

organismal level where another explanation is

43:36

some type of frozen accident happened

43:38

in the past that produces this

43:40

lineage that you know the system

43:43

it's still alive natural selection is still going to

43:45

operate as natural selection

43:47

does as life does it makes the best of

43:49

what it has but to use that to

43:52

sort of expand that out to a full

43:54

way to understand the evolutionary process that

43:56

seems to be ambitious. Well you see what

43:58

I'm trying to do is to make an argument that

44:01

says, look, it's because phenomena

44:03

like that are relatively rare,

44:06

that the language of agency has

44:08

any purchase at all in

44:11

an evolutionary context. In

44:14

that we have this sort

44:17

of general philosophical line of

44:19

argument which says something like, look,

44:22

talk of intention, goal,

44:24

belief and desire is

44:27

really only appropriate when there is

44:29

a kind of rational integration indicative

44:33

of the fact that in cases, say,

44:35

of multiple personality then we really

44:37

struggle to say what on earth it is that a

44:39

person, you know, whether there really is one

44:41

person there at all or what it is that they believe

44:43

or what it is they want. We can't say it. You

44:46

know, the psychological language just ceases to

44:48

apply in that sort of case.

44:50

And what I'm arguing is that we have

44:53

a kind of biological analog of that in

44:55

the sense that if there were

44:57

too much intragenomic conflict, the

45:00

phenotypic consequences of

45:02

that would make it impossible for

45:04

us to think of the organism

45:07

as trying to achieve anything and

45:09

it would be impossible to metaphorically

45:11

characterize it as, you know,

45:13

aiming at some goal or other,

45:16

if you like. So I guess

45:18

I'm suggesting that this psychological integration

45:20

and rational integration is a necessary

45:22

condition of applying psychological language literally.

45:25

And the biological phenotypic integration

45:28

that one gets when intragenomic conflict

45:30

is effectively suppressed, as in the

45:32

vast majority of extant

45:35

organisms, is the necessary condition

45:38

of applying that psychological

45:40

language metaphorically to organisms.

45:43

And we see those types of conflicts not

45:45

only inter-genomically, but we

45:48

also see those conflicts, for example, between

45:51

the goals of males versus females and

45:53

how those play out, you know, in

45:55

terms of toxic sperm that may help

45:57

an individual male against set of conditions.

46:00

competitors but actually does harm to

46:02

the female. And so it's

46:04

the same conceptual framework that we're applying

46:06

in those cases as well. But in

46:08

that case, the conflict is between genes

46:10

in different organisms, I guess, or between

46:13

two separate organisms. Yeah. Or

46:15

yeah, two sexes, I guess. So

46:17

for that very reason, I think it would

46:20

be a mistake to think that a mating

46:22

pair was agent-like, if

46:24

you see what I mean, or to talk about what

46:26

the mating pair is trying to achieve. Obviously,

46:29

their interaction is partially mutualistic.

46:31

You use the term integration,

46:33

but also, I think

46:35

along with that, you also use the

46:37

term unity of purpose. And

46:40

so I think that's

46:42

the outcome of the integration, that

46:44

these actions are towards the goal,

46:46

towards this purpose, and it requires

46:48

this integration or coordination to achieve

46:51

that goal. Absolutely. But

46:54

I mean, one thing I do stress is that it's a matter

46:56

of degree. So there

46:58

are local violations of this unity of

47:01

purpose do certainly exist, and there are

47:04

relatively common in intra-genomic conflict, as you

47:06

guys all know, has been found in

47:08

almost every tax of where it's been

47:10

looked for. But nonetheless,

47:12

I do think that those

47:15

violations are necessarily local, if you

47:17

like, in that if you had

47:19

too much breakdown of unity

47:21

of purpose, you probably wouldn't

47:23

actually have an organism at all. And

47:26

you certainly wouldn't be able to think of

47:29

it as akin to a rational agent trying

47:31

to achieve an end to which its various

47:34

phenotypes all contribute. Yeah.

47:37

So I have a related question here that

47:39

builds on what you just said about the

47:41

idea of whether a mating pair

47:43

has agency, and that's just to

47:46

expand, it's also kind of a

47:48

levels question, but going in the other direction,

47:51

and thinking about groups of organisms and

47:53

whether or not they show agency and

47:55

how that relates to their evolutionary processes.

47:57

And like at some level, It's

48:00

easy to think of groups

48:02

that almost certainly do have

48:05

agency like U.S. Social Insect

48:07

Colonies in which many of the individuals are

48:09

closely related to one another and they act

48:12

essentially like a super organism.

48:15

But what about, say, interspecific

48:17

groups which occur

48:19

all the time in the wild? And I'm

48:21

thinking of things like, so there's a

48:24

retired professor here at Montana, Eric

48:26

Green, whose work some on communication

48:29

among different bird species in between

48:31

mammals and birds in forests. And

48:34

you may be aware of some of this work,

48:37

but there are waves of communication about predators

48:40

that travel between the members

48:42

of these interspecies groups. And

48:45

that really define a lot about where

48:47

these individuals go and, you know, when

48:49

they're feeding and when they're being fearful

48:51

and paying attention to predators

48:54

that are coming by. So would you

48:56

say that a large multi-species

48:58

group like that also shows agency

49:00

in some way? I

49:02

guess I would hesitate to say that,

49:05

although it might be true. I mean, I don't

49:07

think you could rule it out, definitely. But I

49:09

think the reason I would hesitate to say it

49:12

is just for the same reasons

49:14

that people have always been

49:16

reluctant to think of such a

49:18

multi-species group as an adapted unit

49:20

itself. I mean, clearly

49:22

the organisms in it are adapted and

49:25

in part they're adapting themselves to

49:28

the social environment that

49:30

they find themselves in, which includes

49:32

living in these multi-species communities. But

49:34

that's still different from saying that,

49:37

you know, the multi-species group itself is adapted.

49:39

I mean, this goes back to the point

49:41

that George Williams made way back in 1966

49:43

in his book Adaptation and Natural

49:46

Selection, where he

49:48

wanted to say, look, distinguish between a

49:51

group adaptation and a fortuitous

49:53

group benefit. We

49:55

can't really easily conceive of

49:58

an evolutionary process by which species

50:00

groups could have come to be

50:02

the adapted units themselves. Although,

50:04

I mean, it's possible. Because their

50:07

evolutionary interests are not closely enough

50:09

aligned consistently, right? Right,

50:11

exactly. Yeah, because we would think of

50:13

the evolutionary process as taking

50:16

place on the separate lineages

50:18

within those multi-species groups. And

50:21

to think of, you know, the multi-species group

50:23

as really part of the environment relevant

50:25

to the evolution of the, of

50:28

the populations, the

50:30

con-specific populations that

50:32

make them up. So, I mean, I think

50:34

that's the reason that I would hesitate to

50:37

apply the language of agency here. But

50:39

I would want to say that it

50:41

is ultimately an empirical question that, I

50:43

mean, there are people who, who take

50:45

seriously the idea of community level, natural

50:47

selection, where the community can

50:49

be a multi-species aggregate

50:52

of some sorts. But

50:54

I think if we sort of relax

50:57

the definition of integration, and I think

50:59

another way to capture integration is, is

51:02

to call it some degree of cooperation,

51:04

whether it's at the

51:06

whole organism level, you have to

51:08

have these coordinated responses. I

51:11

could also see cooperation, you know,

51:13

obviously within a group, but if

51:15

we kind of relax a little

51:17

bit what we, what we mean

51:19

by cooperation, I could see it

51:22

also applying to the examples that Art was

51:24

giving of, you know, mixed species,

51:26

because ultimately then

51:28

through that cooperation, what

51:31

emerges is this unity of purpose.

51:33

They all have the same interests

51:35

in avoiding the predators. Yeah,

51:37

I mean, I think that that's possible,

51:40

presumably that, that overlap of evolutionary

51:43

interests will be kind of

51:45

contingent, if you like, and

51:48

could break down. Especially if some of

51:50

those bird species are

51:52

also competitors and don't

51:54

have, under other

51:56

contexts, aligned differences. So yeah,

51:59

I think that kind of context

52:01

dependency probably plays an important role.

52:04

Right. But and of course, even if

52:06

the groups were not conspecific, you know,

52:08

comprised of a single bird

52:10

species, then I mean, it would still

52:12

be problematic to think of the

52:14

group of such a group as, as

52:17

an adapted unit automatically. I mean,

52:20

because I mean, I again, I would be happy

52:22

with that if a demonstrable

52:24

process of group level selection

52:26

has shaped the evolution of

52:28

some phenotype. So then

52:30

we get back into this question of, you know,

52:32

what sort of selection process is necessary

52:34

in order to produce an

52:36

adapted group, as opposed to

52:38

a group of adapted individuals, which

52:41

I've always thought is a helpful

52:43

framing that distinction that the Williams

52:45

made. Yeah. Do you

52:48

think that groups of humans, given

52:50

what we were just talking about with individuals within

52:53

a bird population, would groups of humans count as

52:55

a gentle or do you have to have the

52:57

same qualifiers for us? I

53:00

mean, I think potentially. So, I

53:04

mean, if you think, for example, of not

53:06

a group of humans, like a tribe

53:08

or a, but something more smaller, like

53:11

say committee, or something like that,

53:13

many people in philosophy of social

53:15

science take very seriously the idea that groupings

53:18

like committees can quite literally, literally

53:21

be agent like, we can talk

53:23

literally about what the committee believes

53:26

and decides and did. And

53:28

that certainly is manifested in the way we talk

53:30

ordinarily, we say, yeah, you know, the

53:32

firm raised prices, the committee decided what

53:35

to do, we do use this

53:37

language of choice and decision and

53:39

belief. And there's

53:41

a standard psychological language to

53:45

groupings of humans in

53:47

certain contexts. And

53:49

so I'm happy with the idea that that

53:51

could indeed be literally true. Yeah. And certainly

53:54

that it could be heuristically useful to think

53:56

that way. But again, only I mean, only

53:58

of course, under certain and circumstances. I mean,

54:00

if the committee couldn't come to a decision

54:02

or if, you know, one person on

54:05

the committee said, said X and the other said

54:07

not X, then of course we

54:09

couldn't sensibly talk about what the committee think

54:12

about the topic. So

54:25

we want to transition more directly

54:27

into the interplay between agency, your

54:29

ideas about agency and classic evolutionary

54:31

theory. So to put

54:33

this in an explicitly evolutionary perspective, and

54:36

we could stick with humans or we

54:38

can go in any direction you'd like,

54:41

is there evidence or do you expect that

54:45

in nature there is heritable variation

54:47

for agency? I think as

54:49

you were talking about agency there, it wasn't obviously

54:52

in the adaptive, the classic evolutionary adaptive

54:54

sense, but in natural

54:56

populations, what do you think about heritable

54:58

variation for agency? Well, I

55:01

suppose I would say, you know,

55:03

agency depends on, in any

55:06

of the senses that we've been discussing, it depends on

55:08

the possession of

55:10

certain phenotypes, such

55:12

as, you know, information processing,

55:15

sensing the environment, cognitive

55:18

abilities of various sorts. And

55:20

there must of course have been heritable variation

55:23

in all of those for them to evolve,

55:26

whether there still is now, is perhaps

55:28

slightly different question. But I still think

55:30

of that, I think of the heritable

55:32

variation as being with respect to phenotypes

55:34

that prerequisites

55:36

of or building blocks of

55:39

agency, rather than thinking of

55:41

agency itself as being something that

55:44

is itself a phenotype. Huh,

55:47

that's interesting. So you

55:49

wouldn't call agency itself a trait for

55:52

which there would be heritable variation? No,

55:54

I think it would, I think it's

55:56

almost at the wrong level itself to

55:58

be a trait. But

56:01

that raises a sort of an

56:03

interesting problem for me because, you

56:05

know, if we go back to Fischer, he

56:08

talked a lot about, in his

56:10

fundamental theorem, he talked about essentially

56:13

heritability for fitness. And

56:15

yet fitness is also made

56:17

up of all of these other components.

56:21

And so I see a lot of parallels there,

56:23

but yet in our models we don't have a

56:25

problem thinking about, you know, as long

56:27

as there's additive genetic variance for fitness.

56:30

And maybe that's because we're thinking about

56:32

it at a population level as opposed

56:34

to individual level. Yeah,

56:36

no, I mean, I think that's

56:38

an absolutely fair point. Yeah, so

56:40

if we take it that, you

56:42

know, fitness ultimately depends on the

56:44

vital rates, birth and the

56:47

death rates, and that

56:49

those that contribute to many, many different

56:51

phenotypes, of course, will contribute to the

56:54

vital rates of an organism of

56:56

any sort. So how is it

56:59

then that we're happy to talk about

57:01

heritability of fitness? Yeah, I

57:03

mean, I see the point. You're

57:05

saying, well, why by parody of argument, why

57:07

can't we talk about agency

57:10

as a heritable trait or

57:12

something exhibiting heritable variation? I

57:14

mean, in part, maybe the difference is in

57:16

part just that it's not so easy how you would

57:18

measure it. Yeah, I agree. Right.

57:22

Yeah, I mean, so do we find

57:24

an organism that's got more of it than

57:26

one that's got less of it? I

57:29

mean, how would you? Yeah, right. What does that

57:31

mean to see a population in which there's a distribution

57:33

of agencies, right? Yeah, no, that's

57:35

right. But nonetheless, I mean,

57:37

if we take it that in contemporary

57:39

biological populations, then we do see agency.

57:43

And presumably, if we go far enough back

57:45

in their evolutionary ancestors, then we don't

57:48

find agency or at

57:50

least only precursor forms of it, then some

57:52

evolutionary process must have taken place to produce

57:55

it. So in that sense,

57:57

it's got to be an evolved attribute. But

58:00

I'm still a little bit uncomfortable with thinking

58:02

of it itself as a trait, in

58:05

part just because it seems hard

58:07

to measure and to depend

58:09

on too many other things that have a

58:11

sort of clearer status as traits, let's say.

58:14

I agree, and I think that

58:16

actually is a point of argument

58:18

between me and Marty and Art,

58:20

that I recognize that organisms

58:23

behave and act

58:25

agentially, but I see

58:28

it more as sort of an

58:30

epiphenomenon. It's an emergent property that

58:32

probably has evolved over time, but

58:34

as an emergent property, it's something

58:36

that in of itself is really

58:38

difficult to, as Art was

58:41

saying, like, you know, plot

58:43

a distribution of agency in

58:45

a population. Absolutely.

58:47

I mean, I suppose someone might

58:49

make the argument, well, you

58:51

know, maybe it's fixed within

58:53

every species of something, so

58:56

it doesn't show any distribution, you know,

58:59

within a human population, for example.

59:01

But then it wouldn't be able to evolve. No,

59:04

but maybe it's evolved already. Maybe it's, you know,

59:06

it's like bipedalism or something. Interesting.

59:09

Well, it's a good thing in evolutionary biology, we

59:11

don't have any other great big emergent words like

59:13

gene and fitness and things like that. So,

59:18

Samir, you spent considerable

59:21

time or space in the

59:23

book focusing on Alan Grafven's

59:25

formal Darwinism project. And I

59:28

think the goal of Grafven is to

59:30

move away from population

59:32

measures of fitness to thinking

59:34

about individual optimization, in

59:37

particular as it relates, you know, to this

59:39

idea of agency. It

59:41

seems like Grafven's goals are

59:44

to separate selection

59:47

from individual optimization. But

59:50

then I think you made this

59:52

point in the book that natural selection may

59:54

not always then lead to

59:57

adaptation. And this

59:59

seems like a very counter... counterintuitive conclusion,

1:00:01

could you help me understand how

1:00:04

those get separated from one another?

1:00:07

How natural selection and adaptation get

1:00:09

separated from one another. Yeah, and

1:00:12

this idea that selection alone

1:00:14

can, in some cases, not

1:00:16

lead to adaptation. Right, yeah.

1:00:19

No, I mean, what I was

1:00:21

getting at with that was just

1:00:23

drawing attention to some points that

1:00:25

are fairly well known among evolution

1:00:27

theorists. Phenomena,

1:00:30

for example, are cyclical dynamics,

1:00:32

right, where even in simple one

1:00:35

locus population genetics then we

1:00:37

can point to certain

1:00:39

circumstances under which equilibrium

1:00:42

will not be attained, but

1:00:44

rather gene frequencies will cycle indefinitely,

1:00:48

never settling down and attaining equilibrium,

1:00:51

even though natural selection is the only force

1:00:53

at work, is the only evolutionary force at

1:00:55

work and it's not a stochastic effect. It's

1:00:58

nothing like that. So I

1:01:00

think simple examples like that seem

1:01:02

to illustrate, you know, fairly clearly,

1:01:04

I think that although we usually think

1:01:06

of natural selection as an

1:01:09

engine for adaptation, as producing

1:01:11

organisms that behave as

1:01:13

if they're trying to achieve some end,

1:01:16

some fitness related end, there's no sort

1:01:18

of logical guarantee that that's got to

1:01:20

be the case. And I think one

1:01:22

sees the same in models of frequency dependent

1:01:24

selection. So if you look in the popular

1:01:27

adaptive dynamics framework for thinking about

1:01:29

that, although the same is true

1:01:31

in other formal frameworks as well

1:01:33

for thinking about frequency dependent selection,

1:01:35

it's not always the case that

1:01:37

natural selection will take the population

1:01:39

to an equilibrium at

1:01:42

which individuals are playing

1:01:44

the optimal strategy conditional on the rest of

1:01:46

the population. I mean, often it

1:01:48

will. And that's the nice case in

1:01:50

which we get an evolutionary

1:01:53

stable strategy as the outcome

1:01:55

of frequency dependent selection. But

1:01:57

unpleasant, nasty, nonlinear.

1:02:00

dynamics are a cyclical dynamics for example and

1:02:02

other things are possible too as people have

1:02:04

known for a long long

1:02:06

time even though natural selection is

1:02:08

the only force at work.

1:02:11

So I think of I mean what Grafon is

1:02:13

doing as I see it is in part a

1:02:15

response to that situation in

1:02:18

that he's trying to say something like well I

1:02:21

mean can we say something about when

1:02:23

natural selection will be to adaptation and

1:02:25

he thinks that there's got to be

1:02:27

an intimate and tight link between them

1:02:29

and I think intuitively that makes sense.

1:02:31

I mean the whole point of the

1:02:33

theory of natural selection was precisely to

1:02:36

explain to phenomena adaptation and

1:02:38

diversity but then we face

1:02:40

this fact that when explicit evolutionary models

1:02:42

are made you know what obviously went

1:02:45

beyond what Darwin himself was

1:02:47

thinking of we find that

1:02:49

natural selection sometimes seems to result in

1:02:51

something that we can't really call adaptation

1:02:54

in any clear sense. So

1:02:56

then we want to say well can we

1:02:58

point out conditions under which

1:03:00

it will and that I think

1:03:03

of as what Grafon is trying to do

1:03:06

in his project and I think it is very

1:03:08

useful I mean although I don't think all the

1:03:10

moves he makes are ultimately successful

1:03:12

I think it's a conception it's extremely useful

1:03:14

to say look on the one hand we

1:03:16

have the process of natural

1:03:18

selection and on the other hand

1:03:20

we have the phenomenon of

1:03:23

adaptation to the environment and the

1:03:25

one is meant to explain the

1:03:27

other and the fitness concept rather

1:03:30

oddly is sort of features

1:03:32

on both sides of that equation. My

1:03:34

follow-up to that is it seems like

1:03:37

there's another concept here that is somehow

1:03:39

lost in the arguments which

1:03:41

is variation and so I

1:03:43

completely agree in the simplistic models

1:03:46

you know we think about selection

1:03:48

leading to adaptation and

1:03:51

the fixation of a single sort

1:03:53

of variant but whether it's

1:03:56

frequency dependence or density dependence or

1:03:58

just if there's fluctuation

1:04:00

environments, it seems like

1:04:03

one outcome of that is that

1:04:05

no single variant will always be

1:04:08

optimal. And a byproduct of that

1:04:10

is that variation is maintained in

1:04:12

the system, in the population in

1:04:14

this case. And so

1:04:17

I'm just kind of curious where

1:04:19

variation among different

1:04:22

agents or different individuals in a

1:04:24

population falls within

1:04:27

this idea. We touched on

1:04:29

this a little bit that

1:04:31

maybe bipedalism evolves and

1:04:33

then becomes fixed. But I feel like

1:04:36

at some level we

1:04:38

have to incorporate variation into

1:04:40

these ideas. Yeah, no, I

1:04:42

mean, absolutely. I mean, I

1:04:44

think everybody would agree that you need variation in

1:04:47

order for there to be natural selection at all.

1:04:50

If all organisms are the same in

1:04:52

some respect then there's no way that

1:04:54

some variants can out proliferate others. Everyone

1:04:56

has the same variants, if you like.

1:04:58

So that I think is presumably common

1:05:00

ground that variation is necessary

1:05:02

for natural selection. But

1:05:04

I mean, there's also a different question of

1:05:07

whether the outcome of

1:05:09

natural selection will be to

1:05:11

preserve variation or

1:05:13

to eliminate it. Yeah, we think about it

1:05:15

eliminating it usually. Right, we do. We do.

1:05:17

But of course, as you rightly point out,

1:05:19

I mean, if there's,

1:05:22

you know, environmental heterogeneity, temporal

1:05:24

or spatial, or a

1:05:27

host of other complications, or

1:05:30

non additive genetics, for example,

1:05:32

then we can have scenarios where

1:05:35

variation, genetic and phenotypic is in

1:05:38

fact preserved by natural selection or

1:05:40

natural selection can lead to adaptive

1:05:42

diversification, for example, as well.

1:05:45

So I sort of starting,

1:05:48

you know, assumption that natural selection will

1:05:50

reduce variation, although, you know, true, usually

1:05:53

for most, for the simplest

1:05:55

sort of natural selection need not always be

1:05:58

right. So. One

1:06:00

of the issues you brought up is that there's lots

1:06:02

of variation in the environment. And so often

1:06:04

there's not going to be a single genotype

1:06:07

that's optimal. Is

1:06:10

it possible that things like plasticity

1:06:12

and then maybe on top of

1:06:14

that, agential behaviors sort of writ

1:06:16

large are a response

1:06:19

to that and evolved outcome to deal

1:06:22

with that very kind of uncertainty,

1:06:24

right? So there's these systems that

1:06:26

are much more flexible over much

1:06:28

shorter time frames than alleles

1:06:31

and genomes are that

1:06:33

allow organisms to deal with

1:06:35

that kind of uncertainty. To deal

1:06:37

with environmental uncertainty. Yeah. Yeah. Yeah.

1:06:41

So you're thinking of an environment

1:06:43

that changes sort of within

1:06:46

the lifetime of an organism.

1:06:48

Yeah, within or between. But I

1:06:50

mean, either way, the systems that

1:06:53

produce these organisms during development inherently

1:06:55

have this sort of flexibility and

1:06:57

plasticity and agency built into them

1:06:59

to sort of compensate for the

1:07:01

fact that, of course, they're not going to have the ideal

1:07:03

alleles at all, the loci. There's no way

1:07:05

they possibly could, right? No,

1:07:07

I mean, I think that that may well be

1:07:09

true. I mean, of course, I

1:07:11

guess it's not the only possible way that national

1:07:14

selection could adapt a species

1:07:17

to environmental uncertainty. So I

1:07:19

mean, I think that's absolutely

1:07:22

right. But I mean, environmental

1:07:24

fluctuations and heterogeneity and uncertainty

1:07:26

are presumably pervasive in

1:07:29

the living world. I mean, pretty much

1:07:31

all lineages must face those. So then

1:07:33

I guess the question is why some

1:07:35

lineages evolved these agent like

1:07:38

behaviours or capacities

1:07:40

for dealing with them, whereas others

1:07:42

didn't. You know, so

1:07:45

an alternative might be to engage in

1:07:47

some sort of debt

1:07:49

hedging or diversification, for

1:07:51

example, where a given genotype produces lots

1:07:53

of different phenotypes in order

1:07:56

to hedge against the environmental

1:07:58

uncertainty. you know, if

1:08:01

one of those feed types will germinate,

1:08:03

whatever the weather turns out to be.

1:08:05

That well-known idea. So for me, the

1:08:07

question is, can

1:08:09

anyone say something sort

1:08:11

of concrete about the particular

1:08:14

sorts of environments that led to

1:08:16

the elements of agency being the

1:08:18

adaptive response as opposed

1:08:21

to sort of sub-agential things

1:08:23

that one finds more widely? Yeah.

1:08:25

Well, Samir, we've really enjoyed the conversation.

1:08:27

I really appreciate your effort. This has been

1:08:30

wonderful. Oh, it's been great. I mean, I

1:08:33

could talk about this stuff all day, as I'm sure you

1:08:35

guys could too. I

1:08:38

think we all could as well. Excellent.

1:08:41

So we always like to wrap with sort of

1:08:43

giving you a blank page to say anything about

1:08:45

the book or future plans or anything else you'd

1:08:47

like to talk about. Is there anything else you

1:08:50

wanted to hit? Not particularly. I'm currently

1:08:52

writing a book about the concept of

1:08:55

fitness and why it's caused so much

1:08:57

controversy and difficulty and why

1:09:00

it's not as simple a matter as it should

1:09:02

be. Okay. The subject for our next conversation,

1:09:04

please let us know. When that

1:09:06

one comes out, that would be wonderful. Okay.

1:09:09

I will. Hopefully this next year. Yeah.

1:09:11

Send us the book when it's out. Okay.

1:09:14

Well, thank you so much. Yeah. Thanks,

1:09:16

Samir. Thank you. My pleasure. Thank you

1:09:18

all. Thanks

1:09:36

for listening. If you like what you hear, let us know

1:09:38

by an ex Facebook, Instagram, or leave a

1:09:40

review wherever you get your podcast. And if

1:09:42

you don't, we'd love to know that too.

1:09:45

Right to us at info at big biology.org.

1:09:47

Thanks to Steve Lane, who manages the website

1:09:49

and Molly McGinn for producing the episode. Thanks

1:09:52

also to Dana Della Cruz for her

1:09:54

amazing social media. Katie Shumary

1:09:56

produces our awesome cover art. Thanks

1:09:58

also to the college of public health. University of

1:10:00

South Florida and the National Science Foundation

1:10:02

for support. Music on the

1:10:04

episode is from Poddington Bear and Tierra in

1:10:07

Costova.

Unlock more with Podchaser Pro

  • Audience Insights
  • Contact Information
  • Demographics
  • Charts
  • Sponsor History
  • and More!
Pro Features