Podchaser Logo
Home
Rawls' Theory of Justice

Rawls' Theory of Justice

Released Thursday, 16th February 2023
Good episode? Give it some love!
Rawls' Theory of Justice

Rawls' Theory of Justice

Rawls' Theory of Justice

Rawls' Theory of Justice

Thursday, 16th February 2023
Good episode? Give it some love!
Rate Episode

Episode Transcript

Transcripts are displayed as originally observed. Some content, including advertisements may have changed.

Use Ctrl + F to search

0:00

This is the BBC. This

0:03

podcast is supported by advertising outside

0:06

the UK.

0:13

Hello. My name is Jonathan Myerson,

0:15

and before you get to your chosen podcast, I

0:17

want to ask you one question. How

0:20

did an insignificant army corporal?

0:22

End up as chancellor of all Germany.

0:26

It's a story that's improbable and

0:28

also a lesson for us all. My

0:31

new podcast, Nazis, the Rotterdam,

0:34

unraversed it in sixteen dramatized

0:36

episodes starring Tom Middersdale,

0:39

Derek Jacoby, Toby Stevens,

0:41

Alexander Blauhaus, and Laura Donnelly.

0:44

Listen wherever you get your podcasts.

0:52

BBC sounds, music, radio,

0:55

podcasts, Thanks for downloading this episode

0:57

in our time. There's a reading list to go with

0:59

it on our website, and you can get news about

1:01

our programs if you follow us on Twitter

1:04

at BBC in our time. I hope

1:06

you enjoyed the program. Hello.

1:08

A theory of justice by John Rawls has

1:10

been called the most influential book

1:12

in twentieth century political philosophy. Rolls,

1:16

nineteen twenty one to two thousand and two,

1:18

drew in his own experience in World

1:20

War II and saw the chance in its

1:22

aftermath to build a new society founded

1:24

on personal liberty and fair equality

1:27

of opportunity. And while

1:29

in that just society that could be inequality.

1:32

Rawls' radical idea was that those inequality

1:34

must be of the greatest advantage, not the richest

1:37

but to the worst of. With

1:39

me to discuss Rawls' theory of Justice

1:41

R Fabian Peter, professor of philosophy

1:44

at the University of Warwick, Martin O'Neil,

1:46

professor political philosophy at the University

1:48

York and Jonathan Wharf, the Alfred Lundlacher

1:51

professor of values and public policy at

1:53

the Patrik School of Governors, University

1:55

Oxford and Fair of Wolfstone College. Let's

1:58

start with you, Martin.

2:01

Can you give us some brief

2:03

notes about his background, his

2:06

news. Sure. So Rawls'

2:08

was born in nineteen twenty one in Baltimore,

2:11

Maryland to quite an affluent family,

2:13

his father was a quite a successful

2:16

lawyer. He was one of five boys.

2:18

And I spoke to the couple the

2:21

most notable incident of his

2:23

childhood was that two of his younger brothers

2:25

died in childhood from infections

2:27

that they'd actually contracted from Rawls'

2:30

himself. So it seems as if

2:32

he with this 4 of experience very

2:34

early in his life, he had this sense of

2:36

the sheer arbitrariness of of good or bad

2:39

luck and the way that so many features of our lives

2:41

really just come down to factors well

2:43

beyond our our control. He

2:45

then went on to Princeton where he studied,

2:48

he did an accelerated degree, given

2:50

the the US entry into World War two,

2:52

and he joined the US Army as a

2:54

private. So he didn't take the route that some of

2:56

his fellow principal men were doing of

2:58

looking for officer commissions. He he joined

3:01

up as a an ordinary soldier and

3:04

fought in the in the Pacific during

3:06

World War two in the Philippines and

3:08

in New Guinea and ended

3:10

up actually at one point on a

3:12

on a troop train going through Hiroshima

3:15

just after the bombing. The war,

3:17

I think, had a con Was he able to continue

3:19

studying wagers in the war? So he

3:21

he just finished his his principal

3:23

degree that had been accelerated. And

3:25

his plan actually after the war

3:27

was that he would enter the Episcapalian priesthood.

3:30

That's what he thought he was gonna do. But the experience

3:33

of the war completely changed his

3:35

life. He lost his faith over

3:37

the course of the war, both the,

3:39

I think, the sense that the

3:41

sheer difficulty of seeing that some of his friends and comrades

3:44

killed when he survived. think it was

3:46

very difficult for him, but also learning

3:48

of the the full evil of of the whole

3:50

course than the the evil of the Nazi regime.

3:52

I think made him him lose his

3:55

his faith that there was any divine plan

3:57

in history or that divine providence

3:59

was going to work its way in the world.

4:01

So I think by the end of the war,

4:03

rules had this very vivid sense that

4:06

the church wasn't going to be him and

4:08

instead he had to think about the project of

4:10

justice as something that human beings themselves

4:13

would have to make in the world. We could and

4:15

trust in in divine providence, but

4:17

instead it had to be something that people

4:19

together created.

4:21

Well, Rosa's working man in the USA.

4:23

Now here's a big one for you. Can you tell us the

4:25

four or five major political and

4:27

social events that were going on in

4:30

in your in your associates in the

4:31

USA. I'm sure you can do that. They

4:33

go the very very straightforward question.

4:35

So well, I mean, after the war,

4:37

so what Rawls' does he goes back on on the

4:40

thanks to the GI bill. He goes back

4:42

to the PHD apprintant. So that's one big

4:44

thing that's happening that you get Yeah.

4:46

The new means of society. All of the big things.

4:48

Well, so you get that experience. So

4:50

I spoke with the new deal you

4:52

get this period where the

4:54

US is heading towards a somewhat more

4:56

equal society where you get that

4:58

expansion of opportunity at

5:01

the time that he's teaching then through

5:03

the sixties. I guess that I don't know about

5:05

four or five issues,

5:08

but I suppose two things that loom very

5:10

large of the fit and war obviously is going

5:12

on in the background and also the civil rights

5:15

movement and issues around the treatment

5:17

of African Americans and the how

5:19

how the US can can become

5:22

a more inclusive society. That's all going

5:24

on in background at the time that Rawls' writing

5:26

in an academic register about

5:28

justice. Could it be described as turbulent

5:30

and con rather confused society that was

5:32

looking for a clear way

5:34

through? I think there's certainly a

5:36

a large amount of turbulent. I think also

5:38

underlying that sense of progress. There's

5:41

some sense of confidence. There's a thought that

5:43

in the wake of the the war and the wake of the

5:45

New Deal that this is a society that's actually facing

5:47

up to to some of its domestic problems

5:50

at least and and, you know, might be moving

5:52

towards becoming a more equal society.

5:54

And I that there's a kind of confidence at that stage

5:57

that maybe disappears later

5:58

on. Thank you. And Joe

6:00

will let's let's go through aspects

6:03

of his of his work now starting with utilitarianism.

6:07

What place did that have in the development of

6:09

his ideas? First of all, tell people what it

6:11

is, and then tell them what place it had in

6:13

his views. Utilatorism

6:15

is the theory really

6:18

systematized or introduced by Jeremy

6:20

Benthem. And the

6:23

thought from Benthem is

6:25

that the juicy of governments and you

6:27

as an individual is to

6:29

pursue the action that will

6:31

bring about the greatest happiness of the greatest

6:34

number. So that is the utilitarian slogan

6:36

society you should bring about the greatest happiness,

6:38

the greatest number. And

6:41

the way that is cashed out in a bit

6:43

more detail is that we

6:45

need to do a type of cost benefit analysis

6:48

of the good and the bad. In

6:50

fact, the happiness unhappiness or pleasure

6:53

and pain that any action will bring

6:55

about. And our duty as an

6:57

individual or as a society is

7:00

to bring about the state of affairs

7:02

that has the greatest balance of

7:05

pleasure over pain or happiness

7:07

over unhappy this. So it's

7:09

a maximizing view that says we

7:11

should, in sense, make society

7:13

as happy as

7:14

possible. And

7:16

On that basis, you can see it's very

7:18

appealing theory that you might think what

7:21

else should government do other than

7:23

how

7:23

do you measure this?

7:25

Well, that is question that every

7:27

great utilitarian has managed to duck rather

7:29

than address directly

7:30

to be part of the duckers. Well,

7:33

it's it's not my theory, so thank So

7:36

it is a very difficult question about how you

7:38

measure and it's very important because

7:40

if you're aggregating something and maximizing it,

7:42

you have to quantify it. And

7:45

this is problem that one has a

7:47

modern economics to some degree as

7:49

well, and they're a technical solution around

7:52

preference satisfaction and measuring the

7:54

gambles that people would take.

7:57

But for Banff and John

7:59

Stewart mill, they they really didn't address

8:01

that in any

8:02

detail. So just to just because the

8:04

start of this conversation about his I

8:06

might hear work. We've got utilityerrorism as

8:09

well and Rawls' it a pillar or a step. Whatever

8:11

it is. And the other is inch intuitionism.

8:15

Lot ofisms about this morning. What

8:18

what do you know about his view of intuitionism?

8:21

In the early sections of a theory of

8:23

justice, Rawls' sets up

8:25

this type of opposition between

8:27

utilitarianism and intuitionism. So

8:30

as we've seen, utilitarianism is

8:33

highly principal view. It gives you really

8:35

a decision procedure for

8:37

public policy, and it allows

8:40

different people to try to

8:42

calculate and come up with the same or different

8:44

results and give us type of principle

8:47

of public accountability. The

8:49

problem with you to serenism, though, is

8:51

that in Rawls'' phrase,

8:54

it ignores the separateness of persons.

8:57

That is If one person

8:59

suffers and another benefits more

9:02

than the other person suffers. If we can measure

9:04

this, then we should go ahead. So

9:06

it doesn't pay any

9:08

attention to individual rights.

9:11

And so if society

9:13

will maximize happiness in a way that

9:15

is detrimental to one group's interests,

9:17

that's just bad luck. So although

9:20

utilitarianism is very principled, it

9:22

can give us counterintuitive consequences.

9:25

And intuitionism is a mirror

9:27

image. So intuitionism

9:30

is the view, roughly speaking, that

9:33

you should do whatever seems right to you

9:35

that we all have moral

9:38

intuitions. We have judgments

9:40

about states

9:41

some of us are very balanced destructive

9:43

thoughts. Well, we do. So so

9:46

an intuitionist must say you've been brought up badly

9:48

if you have those

9:49

thoughts. No.

9:50

How do you that we have to rely on the intuitions

9:52

of those who know best, who turn out to

9:54

the people who've written the theory and

9:56

are from the finest Oxbridge colleges

9:59

on the whole So this is a problem with nutritionism.

10:01

And what we've got here, what Rawls' is done,

10:03

whether it's something

10:05

going on in its own mind or a

10:08

type of historical development is

10:10

replaying something that comes up time and time again

10:12

in public policy. Because on the one hand,

10:16

We want rules, we want

10:18

accountability, we want something

10:20

that is public and transparent. But

10:22

problem with any system of rules is that very

10:24

often it will give us judgments, outcomes we

10:26

don't like very much. In my

10:28

reading, rules and others may differ.

10:30

How what I see Rawls' is doing is trying to

10:33

get the advantages of both of these theories

10:35

and ignore, overcome the disadvantages.

10:38

So what he wants is a principle that

10:40

only ever gives the right answers

10:42

rather than the tab utility wherein principle

10:45

that will sometimes give us unjust outcomes.

10:47

Fermión, Peter, there's an element of

10:50

the social contract Rawls' approach.

10:52

Can you tell us what that is

10:54

and what part of it he was drawing

10:56

on, please? Yes. Of course. Indeed,

10:59

the social 4 contract edition, which was particularly

11:01

influential in the eighteenth century, played

11:04

a huge part in how Rawls' thought

11:06

about the principles of just this. So

11:08

as Joe and Martin explained,

11:11

Rawls' was trying

11:13

to figure out what a just society would

11:15

look like, and the way he thought about

11:17

this was, what are the principles of

11:20

justice that could govern

11:22

the basic structure or the basic

11:24

social solutions of a

11:26

society. So the

11:28

theory of justice, the book we're discussing starts

11:31

with this wonderful sentence saying

11:34

that justice is the first virtue

11:36

of social institutions. And

11:38

in thinking about the justice of social

11:40

institutions, we all thought that

11:42

it will help if we go back to these influential

11:45

eighteenth century social contract

11:47

thinkers, especially John

11:49

Locke, Jean Jacques, also anyone

11:52

will count. Now, these are very diverse

11:54

thinkers, as I'm sure you know better

11:56

than most, but what United

11:59

them in Rawls' and in views of

12:01

many is that they thought

12:03

about a just social contract,

12:06

a system of principles of justice that

12:09

define in just society that

12:11

define a system that everyone's

12:14

subscribed to would start from

12:16

a commitment to the equal freedom of

12:18

all citizens. So a just

12:20

society is one that all

12:23

citizens, all persons understood as

12:25

free and equal, could degree too.

12:27

They could sign up to that sort of society.

12:29

And Rawls' thought that that was an important

12:32

idea, and he built his justice on that

12:34

idea of what principles of

12:36

justice could, persons understood

12:38

as free and equal, all agreed to.

12:41

Now as I mentioned, this this kind of

12:43

thinking about the Just Society so peaked

12:46

in the eighteenth century. And then

12:48

with the ascent of utilitarianism that Joe

12:50

mentioned, It lost influence. It

12:52

lost influence in part because

12:54

Jeremy bentham, the influential utilitarian

12:57

thinker, ridiculed the idea, and

12:59

particularly he ridicule the idea of

13:02

people are somehow naturally equal and

13:04

equally free. That's how he ridiculed

13:06

the idea of natural rights. That's

13:08

how everyone would have equal rights. He called

13:10

that nonsense upon stilts. So

13:13

when Rolfs set out in the twentieth, I'm

13:15

sure he was to think about justice, he thought,

13:17

well, you did deteranism has

13:20

these advantages, but one big problem

13:22

is it doesn't actually give us

13:24

the right answers on justice. So

13:26

to make progress on thinking about what the society

13:29

looks like, we should go back to these earlier

13:31

thinkers. And start again

13:33

from this thought is if we all understand

13:36

each other as

13:36

equals, what could we all agree to?

13:38

Would it just society look like? So

13:41

what did he think if it's possible him

13:43

a brief about this. And if it is, it is. If it isn't,

13:45

it isn't. What what what what overall

13:47

was his

13:47

view? What's his theory of justice?

13:50

His theory of justice, he calls is justice

13:53

as fairness is a

13:55

theory that is based on two

13:57

main principles of justice. A

14:00

first principal, the principle of equal liberties

14:03

holds that, you know, just society, all

14:05

members of society enjoy

14:08

an equal set of basic rights and

14:10

live So that's the first principle. The

14:12

second principle of justice that he would that

14:14

he thought define the justice society is

14:17

the sort of principle. Everyone could three

14:19

two, like the first one, is

14:21

a principle of justice. It has

14:24

two components. One is a

14:26

principle of fair equality of opportunities such

14:28

as society would give everyone fair

14:31

opportunities. And the second part of the second

14:33

principle of justice is a different principle,

14:35

which says that a just society works

14:38

to the benefit of the least well off

14:40

in that

14:40

society. That's

14:41

the radical part. That's the radical part.

14:43

I mean, there the radical elements -- Yeah. -- because

14:45

even the first part, the first principle, the

14:47

principle of equal rights and liberties says

14:49

that of those rights and

14:51

liberties, one aspect is

14:54

the political rights and liberties. And

14:56

there he thought everyone should enjoy a fair

14:58

value, which is a very demanding idea

15:00

that is not enough Everyone has a right to

15:02

vote. Everyone should, in

15:04

fact, have an equal say in society,

15:07

be in a position to be an equal contributing

15:09

member to society. That's already very

15:11

radical, but then the difference principle

15:14

to thought that society should not work

15:16

to the advantage of already better

15:18

off, but benefit the worst off.

15:20

That was

15:20

certainly also very radical. Well,

15:22

thank you for that. That's a very, very good

15:24

start Martin. Martin. So

15:26

let's take this. There's there's three Rawls'

15:29

-- Yeah. -- one and two in

15:31

two parts, so let's go in three. Can

15:33

you tell us, first of

15:34

all, about Liberty that about fair opportunity. What

15:36

his view of Liberty was? So

15:38

I think you got the easy question. Well

15:41

Fabienne has done a very good job

15:43

of introducing that Now I think one

15:45

thing to say to you, absolutely, right, that this is three

15:47

principles, rules of ways that you've got

15:50

two. But actually, given that the

15:52

second vied into two halves. It's much easier

15:54

to think of it as three. So

15:57

Rawls' says there should be, as Fabienne has said, the system

15:59

of equal basic liver things. And that's really

16:02

the kind of familiar liberal freedom

16:04

of expression, freedom of assembly,

16:06

freedom of movement, freedom to

16:08

rights. Well, I mean, maybe

16:11

not yet freedom from faith. There are things that

16:13

just the kind of the basic constitutional rights

16:15

that we'd have in the democratic society.

16:18

But to that Rawls' out this Rawls'

16:20

quite radical writer to

16:22

that idea. So he says it's not

16:24

enough simply if you think

16:26

about the various liberties that we have

16:28

as democratic citizens. It's not enough

16:31

that those are merely formal protections.

16:33

We need what he calls the fair value that

16:35

of the political liberties. So

16:38

what that means Rawls' is

16:40

that for people with a

16:42

similar motor ablation and similar

16:44

ability to intervene in the political

16:47

process. There should be roughly equal

16:49

prospects of getting to influence political

16:52

outcomes. So a political system

16:54

where the interests of the rich

16:57

or privileged gets much more

16:59

weight and the interests of others or

17:01

where certain groups get to, you know,

17:03

become members of parliament and other groups don't.

17:05

That's a society that fails to realize

17:08

the fair value of the political liberties. Even

17:10

if in formal terms, everyone has got the same

17:13

same rights. Now to move to the second

17:15

principle then, when Rawls' talks about this idea

17:17

of fair quality of opportunity, as

17:20

Fabian has said, that's also a surprisingly

17:22

radical idea because it not

17:24

merely the idea that all jobs

17:27

in the economy should be formally open

17:29

to everyone that there shouldn't be discrimination

17:32

on grounds of of rare a sort gender

17:34

or sexual orientation or or whatever it

17:36

it might be. It's the much stronger thought

17:39

that those who with similar motivation

17:43

and ability should have the same prospects of

17:46

success in the economic realm just

17:48

as the earlier principle wants to guarantee

17:50

a fair chance that success in in the in the

17:52

political realm. So those two

17:54

principles together really

17:57

visit your society where none

18:00

of the social facts about people's backgrounds,

18:02

their their social class, their

18:04

race. None of that would actually have

18:06

a material influence on their

18:08

chances of success, whether

18:10

in the political domain or whether in the

18:13

the economic

18:13

domain. Did

18:14

you work out in any way how this could be achievable.

18:16

Does it does it remain a sort of idealistic

18:19

boon? So he he does talk

18:21

about some of what would be involved

18:23

there. I suppose the two main things that

18:25

come up there. On the one

18:27

hand, he talked a little bit about the education

18:29

system. So what he

18:32

envisages there is it's an education system

18:34

that tries to act to overturn

18:37

background inequality. So

18:39

the thought would be that if you've got a society

18:42

where Some some groups

18:44

have advantages that others don't.

18:46

You try and design an education system that

18:48

actually targeted more resources at

18:50

those coming into it from relatively just

18:52

answered background to try to

18:54

equalize life chances. Another

18:56

big part of of that would then

18:59

be the tax system. So

19:01

Rawls', because he's so interested in these

19:04

two different kinds of fair quality of opportunity

19:06

in the political domain and the

19:08

economic domain. He's very worried about

19:10

the intergenerational transmission of advantage,

19:13

the way that well health in one generation

19:15

turns into unfair opportunities

19:18

in the next generation. And he thinks

19:20

that what we need to do is design a tax

19:22

them that tries to to fight against that.

19:24

So he endorses high

19:27

levels of inheritance taxation or

19:29

capital transfer taxation. He

19:31

thinks 4 what we need is a a fiscal

19:34

structure that stops this kind of build up of

19:36

of enormous wealth across generations that

19:38

turns into unfair levels of

19:41

advantage from generation to generation. Thank

19:43

you, Albert. Joe, what

19:46

do we know about the difference principle? Well,

19:49

one

19:49

thing I think we know

19:51

is that it is a highly

19:53

original principle. Rawls'

19:57

was a very modest man. And if you look through

19:59

a theory of justice, virtually every

20:01

idea he

20:02

has, he tries to find someone who had it before

20:04

four. So the the book is just peppered.

20:06

He

20:06

just wanted to show off. Yeah. He didn't want

20:08

to show off. He was a very modest man. But

20:11

he can't find anyone to pin the difference principle

20:13

on as far as I can see. There there are one or two

20:16

shadows 4 shadowings of

20:18

it. And maybe one way of using

20:20

it is that in the British

20:22

Labour Party in the nineteen 4,

20:26

there was 4 debate about equality.

20:30

And some

20:32

people wanted to complete equality

20:34

of income and off. But that lays

20:36

you open to an easy critique

20:38

that equality takes away

20:41

incentives. And so if we divide everything

20:43

who's going go to work. You know, who where

20:46

is the juice that run society

20:48

going come from? So

20:51

these simple theories of equality were not

20:53

really in favor. But the Labour Party

20:56

said inequality is

20:58

just viable as long as it works to everyone's

21:01

advance message. So it has to be

21:03

inequality for the sake of everyone. And

21:05

what I think did was just

21:08

we're still a

21:08

difference. We're on the difference principle. And the

21:10

qualities of income and wealth

21:14

are to be to the advantage of everyone. But

21:16

rawls, I think ratchets up a

21:18

notch and says it's not just that they've got to be

21:20

to the advantage of everyone. They've got to

21:23

make the worst off as well off as possible.

21:25

So if we'll try to judge the

21:28

justice of our society. We

21:31

should look to the income and wealth,

21:33

not of the worst off individual because that could

21:35

give us quite arbitrary results, but but identify

21:38

the worst off group, whoever

21:40

they may be, the lowest paid workers,

21:42

unemployed people, and

21:45

if we could improve their

21:47

position without making anyone else fall

21:49

below where those people were, then

21:52

our society is unjust. So

21:54

just as requires us to make the worst off

21:57

group as well off as possible.

22:00

And as far as I know, no society has

22:02

ever achieved anything. Even

22:04

close to that. So it's not just about redistribution,

22:07

it's not just about high tax, but

22:10

arranging a 4 society where there were

22:12

stuff can flourish as much

22:14

as is possible. What do you think

22:16

if it is an idea? Well,

22:18

it's a lovely idea. Yeah. I think I I'm

22:20

I'm

22:20

pushing do you think would be on that? Is it

22:22

achievable? Well, so I would love

22:24

to live in that society. There

22:26

are several ways in which might not

22:28

be achievable. One is whether it may -

22:31

it's not economically achievable.

22:34

And I don't see any reason to think that

22:37

it couldn't be achievable.

22:39

It may be not through tax

22:41

and transfer. Maybe we'd have to completely

22:43

reorganize society in his

22:45

later work, rawls use

22:47

the idea of a property owning

22:49

democracy. So the idea that we disperse

22:52

wealth. So it's not about redistribution. It's

22:54

allowing everyone on to live their own

22:56

lives to the best of their abilities. So

22:59

I think economically, it's

23:01

a feasible dear for as much as I know about it.

23:04

Politically, it hasn't got a chance.

23:07

And I think this goes back to

23:09

point Martin was making about

23:11

the fair value of political liberties because

23:14

for as long as we've got system which

23:16

allows wealthy people to spend a lot of money

23:18

getting elected, then we're not going

23:20

to have policies that

23:23

redistribute wealth in the way that Rawls' would

23:25

want want. Thank you. Fabienne,

23:28

BTEC. This is Thierry,

23:30

one of our biggest call there, appears

23:33

to go the original

23:34

position. Now can you tell about them.

23:36

Indeed. So the original position is

23:38

one of the many sort of long

23:40

lasting ideas that we find in

23:42

the theory of just this. The theory

23:44

of justice Rawls' pressure drug, I

23:47

would say, of novel ideas,

23:49

ideas that have caught on

23:51

and influence philosophy a great deal.

23:54

The original position is one of them.

23:56

It's a thought experiment that helps

23:58

us to illustrate the

24:00

social contract approach to thinking

24:03

about just society. So

24:05

as I explained earlier, the social contract

24:07

approach that world stakes what

24:09

is the set of principles that persons

24:12

understood as 4 and equal can

24:14

agree to? Now what's this sort

24:16

of agreement that we're talking about here?

24:19

The problem is if we think about

24:21

the agreement starting from

24:23

everyone's actual position in

24:25

society tea. They might be

24:27

biased towards their privilege.

24:29

That's one problem. Or the

24:31

better off might try to buy

24:33

off the worse off to an an overall

24:36

agreement that ends up benefiting the

24:38

better off. So we can't really

24:41

take our actual starting points because

24:43

that there's too much in quality baked

24:45

in the actual society as we

24:47

know it. So the original position

24:49

is a thought experiment that helps us illustrate

24:52

What would an agreement look

24:54

like if it was reached from a starting

24:56

point of equality? And the

24:58

way in which World's South Experiment

25:00

works he thinks we

25:02

can imagine

25:04

ourselves in a position of equality.

25:07

If we imagine that we're thinking about

25:10

the justice society from behind a

25:12

veil of ignorance. This veil

25:14

of ignorance led through

25:16

information about our society

25:19

general, how it works, how the

25:21

economy works, what social dynamics

25:23

are, but it doesn't through any

25:25

information about who we are in that

25:27

society. Hold

25:28

on. So we're all behind

25:30

this bail. That's Right. Everybody. Everybody.

25:33

A set of representatives. Up to charge

25:35

with finding

25:36

justice. Yep. So how does the

25:38

thing Right? Do we take off the vial

25:40

though? Can you just take this

25:42

out? Quick. Like, on a basic

25:44

step forward. Okay. Good. So

25:47

in the first instance, it helps us a straight

25:49

position of equality. So if

25:51

you don't know whether you're rich or poor,

25:54

whether you're what your gender

25:56

identity is, what your races,

25:59

Ben Ward hoped, you'd

26:01

be more inclined to think

26:04

about what justice requires in

26:06

a way that's not biased by your current

26:09

position and that will be helpful in reaching

26:11

an overall agreement. However,

26:13

of course, Being behind

26:15

this veil of ignorance is not helpful

26:17

if we're trying to make these principles

26:19

of justice that we just heard about more concrete.

26:22

So the way in which we'll about it is

26:24

that there's a 4 stage sequence. The

26:26

first stage is what would adjust

26:28

society even look like? That

26:30

deliberation happens behind the veil of

26:33

ignorance. But when we then try to

26:35

make it more concrete than workout

26:37

principles that can be implemented in society,

26:39

this veil is gradually lifted under

26:42

the end at the stage of making laws,

26:44

all information is available. But

26:46

the thought is still the deliberation about

26:48

what should our laws be like.

26:50

It's constrained by an idea of justice

26:53

reached in a deliberative process where

26:55

we're less influenced by our own ideally

26:57

not influenced by our bias

27:00

is or thinking about our

27:02

advantages given our actual positions

27:04

in society.

27:05

Thank you. March, do you want to take that

27:07

one? Yes. So I suppose

27:09

one way thinking about how the vagal

27:11

ignorance functions. It it's

27:13

a sort of radicalization of

27:16

the the social contract relation. It's thinking

27:18

not not what you and would agree to

27:21

if, you know, if you've got some threat advantage

27:24

over me, if I'm sort of worried about what you

27:26

can do to me. If we could strip away anything

27:28

that makes an agreement unfair. So

27:30

the fact that we have different starting points and

27:32

we can get abstract away from all of

27:34

that and then think, well, what would we agree

27:36

to in general terms about the construction

27:39

of our society. That's a way of capturing

27:41

through an idea of of of

27:43

choice or bargaining under conditions of

27:46

of ignorance. It's a way of capturing an idea

27:48

of of impartiality. And

27:50

so if you like,

27:52

it's a kind of the original position behind the

27:54

valobigner. It's something it's something

27:57

that we could enter any of us at any

27:59

time. It's a thought experiment. It's a

28:01

way of trying to give some sort

28:03

of Joe was talking earlier about the

28:05

the ambition and rules for some sort of going

28:07

beyond mere intuitionism. What

28:09

the original position does is it gives you

28:11

a kind of imaginative mechanism

28:14

for turning what might be sort of in Kuwait

28:17

moral intuitions and

28:19

and sort of bundling them towards a definite

28:22

set of a definite procedure

28:24

for getting a set of principles for 4

28:26

how society ought to be governed. And that

28:28

in a way that that takes away all the

28:30

kind of the impure of real world

28:32

agreement that that often

28:34

reflect, as Fabienne was saying, background inequality.

28:36

Joe? So there's one thing we're all says

28:39

I think which helps bring the idea to

28:41

life. And he says imagine

28:44

how you would design society if

28:46

you knew that your enemy was going to assign

28:48

you your place in it. And

28:51

then if I remember correctly, he says

28:53

immediately after that. But we shouldn't reason from false

28:55

premises. So, no, this is

28:57

just a type of heuristic. But the the

28:59

idea is if it's rather

29:01

sweet to think you have an enemy, but assume

29:03

you have an enemy, and that person was assigning

29:05

you a place, you would want to make

29:07

the worst place in society as good as possible.

29:10

And and this Rawls'' idea. If you're

29:12

looking at this in completely partial

29:14

way, not knowing where you're going to end up in society,

29:17

then you would design a just society, he

29:19

thinks. I I mean, to to put it bit

29:22

simply terms. If if you're dividing

29:24

a birthday cake among some children, you

29:27

don't want someone to be choosing the slice

29:29

that they've cut. Right? So

29:31

if you get one child to cut the cake and the other

29:34

child to choose which slice they get,

29:36

that's a way of it. They're gonna cut the missing click

29:38

as possible. And Rawls', it it's

29:40

just that that very simple thought

29:42

about how if you don't get to choose

29:45

which place you occupier in society loyalty.

29:47

But you are choosing what the distribution

29:49

of those places look like. You're going to be as fair

29:51

as possible.

29:52

Yeah. Can I come back to you, Joe?

29:56

What's a distinction between justice and

29:58

fairness? Well, I'm glad you asked

30:00

that question because the

30:02

Rawls' describe his views, justice is fair

30:05

us. And it has left people

30:07

scratching their heads and particularly

30:09

translators. Because in many languages,

30:11

they're actually isn't a distinction as

30:14

far as I know between

30:16

justice and fairness. But

30:18

in the English language, there is difference between

30:21

these terms And the one way

30:23

of thinking about is think about the

30:26

infant school. So

30:28

children in

30:31

their infancy have a very strong

30:33

sense of fairness. Things no. That's

30:35

or rather unfair. Say that's

30:37

unfair. So a four year old might say

30:39

that's unfair. But if the

30:41

same four year old said, if that's unjust,

30:44

we'd be a bit surprised. I think there

30:46

there is a parent or high court

30:48

judge or a philosopher. And so,

30:51

justice seems to have a type

30:53

of depth to us and maybe

30:55

formalism that fairness doesn't.

30:58

So fairness is, for

31:00

rawls, largely a procedural

31:03

matter. So as

31:05

I understand it, I think by justice

31:07

as fairness, he simply means that the way

31:09

that we get to adjust outcome is

31:12

through fair procedures. And the

31:14

original position is a way

31:16

in of ignorance is a way of having a fair procedure.

31:18

And if we get the procedure

31:20

right, then we will get a just outcome at

31:22

the other end. You're nodding away.

31:26

Yes. So the idea of procedural justice

31:28

is an essential contribution of

31:30

Rawls', and it links back to what we said earlier

31:32

about his focus was being on the justice

31:35

of the basic structure of society that is

31:37

the set of society's basic institutions

31:39

because we could also think about justice as

31:42

the justice of person. Right? What is a just

31:44

person? Or we could think about justice

31:46

as what do we or we to

31:48

each other individually, but both

31:51

thought these were all questions

31:53

that we can't really resolve at the social

31:55

level, but we can make progress in

31:57

thinking about justice. If we focus

32:00

on if we adopt a procedural

32:02

idea of justice where we get

32:04

the basic institutions of society right,

32:07

have them being governed by some

32:10

small set of principles of

32:11

justice, and then whatever outcome results

32:13

is And the original

32:15

mean, criticisms of the theory. The

32:17

theory of of the Bay of England. Sorry.

32:19

There are a few I'm

32:22

gonna start, you know, maybe perhaps just mentioned

32:24

some. So one influential set

32:26

of criticisms against the original

32:29

position and the bail of ignorance

32:31

came from a set of social philosophers, which

32:33

were known as the communitarians at the

32:36

time. So

32:38

the issue they had with

32:40

Rawls' is thought experiment moment was

32:43

that one feature of

32:45

the original position, as Rose described

32:47

it, is he thought of people behind the veil

32:49

of ignorance as mutually disinterested. And

32:52

he did that because he thought, well, one of

32:54

the circumstances of justice is

32:56

that we are not all maximally

32:59

altruistic. So it'd be misleading

33:01

to think about a theory of justice that could

33:04

actually be implemented if we imagine

33:06

that we're all moral saints. We all concerned

33:08

about each other and all trying to do the best

33:11

for each other. He thought the problem of

33:13

justice is one that we're not like

33:15

that. But we're not enemies either.

33:17

Right? But so he thought assuming

33:19

the the people behind the veil of ignorance

33:21

is, mutually, this interest is a good starting

33:24

point. But these social philosophers, these

33:26

community herion thought that this is

33:28

a misleading characterization of

33:30

persons, as persons we are inherently

33:32

social beings. We are

33:36

born throughout connections with others, and

33:38

we live good lives throughout

33:40

connections with others. So

33:42

mutual interestness which they

33:44

thought boils

33:47

down to us just being self interested

33:50

in atomistic beings is

33:52

the wrong starting point for thinking about justice.

33:54

I think that's sort of misconstrual of

33:56

rules. He did not think of

33:58

us as optimistic self interested

34:01

being. And the sort of process of rational

34:03

justification he was interested in

34:05

was not one where we tried to satisfy

34:07

our self

34:08

interest. He was very much one that's driven

34:10

by our sense of justice. Jerry,

34:13

aren't you coming? I wanted to mention

34:16

more recent criticism of

34:18

the valid ignorance. Which

34:20

is that it has, in a way, too much

34:22

ignorance. We talked before

34:24

about the political events going on at

34:27

the time Rawls' was writing one of them

34:29

is a civil rights movement. And

34:32

recently, rawls has come under a lot of criticism

34:35

for not really having a discussion

34:37

of racial justice. In the United States.

34:40

And I suppose

34:42

as an undergraduate student

34:44

in this country, I never noticed this,

34:46

but now when it's brought to your attention,

34:49

it's rather staggering that

34:51

he he writes as if one

34:53

of the greatest transformations in in

34:56

his society hadn't

34:58

taken place. And

35:00

one way in which this criticism has been made in

35:02

recent years was from the Jamaican

35:05

philosopher who worked in North America Charles

35:07

Mills. And one way of

35:09

putting it is that Mills thinks we

35:11

need to know some facts about

35:14

history in order to come up with the

35:16

right theory of justice. And

35:18

one way of trying to explain this is,

35:20

say, suppose American society tomorrow

35:23

implemented rawls as principles a justice.

35:26

Would it be a justice society? And

35:29

Mill says, well, no, it wouldn't. Because

35:31

if we're all we're doing is making the

35:34

worst off as well off as possible, and

35:36

racial minorities are the

35:39

worst off. They will still be the

35:41

worst off after the transformation.

35:44

That is the all water won't

35:46

be changed. It will just be the absolute position

35:48

of the people at the bottom. And

35:51

so Rawls' think that it's

35:53

necessary to have more

35:55

knowledge in the original position so

35:57

that steps can be taken to redress historical

36:00

injustice.

36:04

One rejoined to the interesting

36:06

challenge from Rawls' comes from

36:08

an African American philosopher, Tommy

36:10

Shelby, the same name as the

36:12

character in pinky blinders,

36:15

but a different person. And

36:17

Shelby, says, well, look, bear in mind.

36:19

So talks about the lexical priority of

36:21

his principles. So first of all, equal basic liberties

36:23

then pair quality of opportunity than the difference

36:26

principle. Now think of the work that would be

36:28

done by fair quality of opportunity

36:30

or fair value of the political liberties. That

36:32

says, try to get rid of whatever

36:34

the the the influence of whatever

36:36

background conditions it might be that

36:38

stopping people from having a fair set of

36:40

opportunities within that entity. Now

36:43

Rawls' there talks about people

36:45

having the same opportunities regardless of their

36:47

social class of origin. But

36:49

class there is a placeholder Rawls'

36:51

4 what everywhere exist in that society that's

36:54

structuring people's opportunities. So

36:56

a society that was marked

36:58

by race social injustice as

37:00

actually existing societies are, that look

37:03

to implement Rawls' principles,

37:05

would first of all look to to

37:07

address those those existing injustices.

37:09

And that's all mandated there in in the theory.

37:12

The reason that Rawls' doesn't want to build

37:14

that in to the the version

37:17

of of the theory in the book one might think is because

37:19

this is a work of philosophy that's aspiring to

37:21

a certain sorts of generality. As

37:23

soon as one would then think about its application,

37:25

then, of course, the relevant historical and

37:28

sociological facts would would come

37:30

in. So I think that there's it it's a really

37:32

interesting issue, but there's certainly two two different

37:34

kinds of views

37:35

that that one might have. Sure. I mean, you wanted

37:37

to make comments on Whether there's a related set

37:39

of criticisms and Rawls' idea

37:41

of the Bay of ignorance faced from feminist

37:44

philosophers. And so

37:46

while agree with Martin that class

37:49

is a placeholder and

37:51

it is feminist philosophers who

37:53

have, like, some plus

37:56

years of race argued that the veil of ignorance

37:59

obscures too much. It shields us

38:01

from important experiences of

38:03

injustice. For example, ample

38:06

injustice in the family. Susan

38:08

Moller oaken, for example, argued

38:11

that one problem with the of justice

38:13

that it's completely unclear how

38:15

justice in the family is supposed

38:18

to figure, and that should be a

38:20

learned for us given that one source

38:22

of injustice comes within the family with

38:24

a very with very unequal

38:26

divisions of labor, women doing a

38:28

share of -- the maximum share of

38:31

unpaid labor, caring for children and

38:33

so on. Rawls' then responded

38:36

to that, to some extent, a long similar minds

38:38

that when it comes to problems of

38:40

gender justice, for example,

38:43

as they might arise in

38:45

patterns of fun really life, they

38:47

could be addressed by the theory of justice

38:49

and the sort of thinking of the veil of ignorance

38:52

could be helpful here because the thought if you

38:54

don't know whether you're gonna end up

38:56

as your children's father

38:58

or mother, what would you think

39:01

just society acquired, but

39:03

he also saw their limits. Both

39:05

thought, for example, that the principles of

39:07

justice are not designed to apply to

39:10

family life itself only to

39:12

the background condition conditions in which

39:14

people might then form their families

39:16

and conduct their family lives. And

39:18

so on feminist philosophy, so that's not good enough.

39:21

So I think we these issues are

39:23

still, I think, today, unresolved, whether

39:25

it comes to race or gender. The the

39:27

thing your justice

39:28

struggles. Thank you very much. We're coming near

39:30

then, Martin. He's

39:32

been criticized heavily and constant and

39:35

yet he survived. Moment survived. He's

39:37

read the most read by

39:40

your students and alright. Why

39:43

does he continue you in a position

39:45

of such importance when he attracts so

39:47

much criticism?

39:49

That's a great question. I think it it's because

39:52

the project is so ambitious and

39:54

it's so well executed. The

39:56

level of of ambition is to give, you know, a

39:58

general account of what it would be for

40:00

human beings considered as free

40:03

and equal individuals to

40:05

live together under terms that they could

40:07

all accept. So it's an absolutely central

40:09

foundational question. And

40:11

it's one that he then approaches

40:14

with with enormous theoretical

40:17

firepower sophistication and

40:20

moral seriousness. And

40:22

he gives you both a method for thinking

40:24

about this problem, and he gives you an

40:26

account of of the content of of

40:29

an answer. His his two or three principles.

40:32

Now what that does really is

40:34

to set up a huge sort

40:36

of target for people thinking about

40:39

about those issues. So you might be convinced

40:41

by rules, in which case you'd have one

40:43

sort of reaction. Or there might be various

40:46

things in in that project that you that

40:48

you disagree with. But where you find yourself then

40:50

articulating that disagreement with

40:52

reference to Rawls'' rules' attempts

40:55

to do this. So I think it's

40:57

unsurprising given the

40:59

magnitude of the achievement. This really is

41:02

someone who's managed to write something that that

41:04

will be a classic in political philosophy

41:06

that's read for hundreds of years. III

41:09

would confidently bet. And

41:11

it creates then something to push

41:13

again, something to argue with, And

41:16

even if you disagree with it, engaging with

41:18

it, I think helps to to make your thinking

41:20

about matters of justice more

41:22

rich share and follow-up. So I would

41:24

agree with all of that. Just one additional

41:27

comment. So, Martin said there are two

41:29

parts that method

41:31

and the theory. I would suggest

41:34

as a third, which is an argument as

41:36

well. So that Rawls' says that

41:39

the way to think about justice is in

41:41

this new form of social

41:42

contract. If you do

41:44

that, you will get my theory

41:47

So

41:48

that is the argument, and then you can

41:50

separately assess the theory. So there

41:52

are people who disagree with method. There

41:54

are people who agree with the math say you would get

41:56

a different theory and there are people who don't care

41:58

about the method or the argument and

42:00

say let's just look at the theory. So

42:02

people completely different philosophical temperaments

42:05

that are drawn to the same thing. And

42:08

there's been nothing since anything like it.

42:10

So it has a level of ambition and

42:12

there was nothing before it since probably

42:15

John Stewart mill or Henry

42:17

Siggwick. So we go for decades

42:20

without the work of that

42:22

achievement. We might be waiting another

42:24

fifty

42:24

years, one hundred years for the

42:26

next one. So it really is a magnificent peace.

42:29

And it is characteristic of works

42:31

of philosophy that many more people disagree

42:33

with them than agree with them. I couldn't think

42:35

of a better ending. Thank you very much for that.

42:37

Thank you. And thank very much for Fabienne

42:40

Peter, Mr. Hugh Jervolf and Martin

42:42

O'Neill and our Studio engineer, Michael

42:45

Millam. Next week, the charts

42:47

discovered that electrical resistance

42:49

can disappear at very low temperatures

42:51

and why this matters super conductivity.

42:54

Thanks for listening. And the in

42:56

our time podcast gets some extra time

42:58

now with a few minutes of bonus material

43:01

from Melvin and his

43:02

guests. So can I stop by asking

43:04

you? How does he say we assess

43:06

moral claims? Here,

43:08

we have another one of Rawls' us

43:10

main innovations Rawls'. And that's

43:13

the idea of reflective equilibrium. It's

43:15

a hugely influential idea, but it's obviously

43:18

not a household name. So even when I

43:21

introduce the idea of reflective equilibrium to

43:23

my students, it's usually blank faces

43:25

at first. So what

43:28

is this? Why is reflective equilibrium important

43:30

for Rawls'? Well, it's a method

43:32

of justification. It's a method for

43:35

assessing who has a claim

43:37

when it comes to thinking about

43:39

the principles of a just society. Flowers

43:43

often think about justification in

43:46

ways connected to truth and knowledge.

43:49

So 4, when we ask whether you

43:51

should believe something, we might suggest

43:53

that, well, you're justified in believing this thing

43:55

as long as it's true or you have enough evidence

43:58

that it's true or something Rawls',

44:00

that's not the right way of thinking about justification

44:03

in the moral domain. So when it comes to thinking

44:05

about moral claims, he thought

44:07

that truth can divide us. He was

44:09

worried about people's religious commitments

44:12

that if they thought so if we ask them to think

44:14

about justice from within their

44:16

say religious understandings

44:19

of moral claims. We end up

44:21

fighting. We end up fighting about moral truth.

44:23

We end up thinking about religious truth,

44:25

and that goes back to what Martin

44:28

was saying earlier about his experiences of society.

44:31

So he device a different method

44:33

one that again sort of captures

44:35

the social contract idea that what justifies

44:38

a set of principles of justice is an agreement

44:41

between per understood as equal. So

44:43

what's the connection between agreement and justification?

44:46

That's the key question. And Rawls'

44:48

thought that we can think about justification,

44:51

not in relation to a search for truth,

44:53

but instead of achieving coherence

44:56

between our moral ideas at

44:59

different levels of generality. So

45:02

we might think that to use an example

45:05

from current society, the

45:07

current levels of poverty are

45:09

morally wrong. Like, that would be a particular

45:11

moral judgment, and we might feel quite strongly

45:13

about that. That might something don't easily want

45:16

to get give up. At

45:18

the more general level, we might think a

45:20

society should offer call

45:22

opportunities, or we might think that

45:24

a a society should be married or creating

45:26

a sort of mid level principles. And

45:28

then there's further level of abstractions of

45:30

general theories. Rawls' thought

45:32

that the right way of thinking about what is

45:34

this right set of principles, what

45:37

moral claims should count is

45:39

by trying to reach a coherence across

45:41

these judgments that we think are the

45:43

right ones at different levels of of

45:45

generality. In addition, he

45:48

thought reflective equilibrium isn't

45:50

just something we can achieve individually by

45:52

going back and forth without anything being

45:55

given, trying to create a consistent

45:58

model view. We can't just

46:00

do that individually. We also do this

46:02

in person least. So the way he

46:04

labeled this as a full reflective equilibrium.

46:07

That's a reflective equilibrium reached

46:10

by a set of people. So

46:12

if we agree across

46:14

people that a certain

46:17

set of principle justice is the right one.

46:19

That's a full reflect active equilibrium. That

46:22

defines which moral claims

46:24

we should honor in society.

46:27

I suppose one thing, it might

46:29

be useful mention is the degree

46:31

to which rules is or isn't a critic of capitalism.

46:34

And think this is something that that's perhaps

46:36

come to be better understood more recently.

46:39

In part because Rawls' Royce's view

46:42

over the course of his life actually seemed to harden

46:44

somewhat and become a bit more disappointed about

46:47

the direction of travel of world

46:49

he was in. So we we talked at

46:51

the outset about the context in the nineteen sixties

46:53

and seventies of the society that in some ways

46:56

was making strides towards greater quality

46:58

and where one might have seen Rawls' theory

47:01

as as just a call for for an acceleration

47:03

of tendencies that that were already be

47:05

there. But I think in in the world

47:08

that we've seen in the last forty years in

47:10

the the the neo liberal period,

47:12

if you like, we've we've moved further and further

47:14

away from something like a just society

47:16

by Rawls'' likes. And I think in

47:18

response to that, rules' own view

47:21

became more more explicitly

47:23

critical of capitalism. So as as Joe

47:25

mentioned earlier, he he

47:27

came to emphasize more the fact that

47:29

familiar kinds of redistributive

47:32

capitalist welfare states, even if they do

47:35

quite a good job of looking after the

47:37

the lease well off, aren't really getting as

47:39

close enough to adjust society. So

47:41

he talked on the one hand about what he called

47:43

property owning democracy, which would be a

47:45

kind of markets economy with

47:48

a a very broad distribution of

47:50

holdings of wealth and

47:52

capital. Or on the other hand, he also

47:54

talked about the idea of a liberal socialist

47:57

regime, which would be more of

47:59

a an economy with more public and collective

48:01

ownership. But but with the same kind

48:03

of protections of individual liver

48:06

tease that he thought were needed

48:08

for just society. So when

48:11

rules actually turn towards thinking about institutions

48:13

and thinking Rawls' existing sets of

48:15

of economic and political regimes.

48:18

He, interestingly, was

48:21

very critical both of sort of

48:23

Soviet style command economies, but

48:25

also of of his own

48:27

country, of the US, as a

48:29

kind of market society that that simply

48:31

wasn't doing enough to move towards

48:34

realization of of his principles. And

48:36

actually, given given various various

48:38

of its structural features, maybe couldn't do

48:40

enough to move towards just society.

48:43

So I think while Paul

48:45

Rawls'' ubiquitousness in

48:47

in academic discussions has

48:49

maybe made him like, quite a familiar intellectual

48:52

figure. I think it would be a mistake to

48:54

think of him as a theorist of the the status

48:56

quo. He's actually someone with quite a

48:58

radical critique of the kind of societies

49:01

we're in. And he's someone who's really pointing

49:03

towards a a very different kind of

49:05

economic settlement and a much more equal

49:07

kind of society than the ones that

49:09

we're in at the moment? Sure. Sure.

49:12

I agree with what has been said.

49:15

There's another question. Of course, about

49:17

Rawls'' influence on policy

49:19

outside the academy. And,

49:21

you know, whether rawls in ideas

49:24

have been taken up. And, of

49:26

course, in some we've gone in the other direction.

49:28

So when Rawls' was writing

49:31

in marginal tax rates in

49:33

the UK and the U. S. At some points

49:35

in the 90s, ninety

49:37

percent it's hard to reconstruct that

49:39

particularly for the U. S. But it

49:41

was true after the war. Marginal tax

49:43

rates were very high. They've come down and down and down.

49:46

So in some ways, it looks like the

49:48

legacy is the opposite of what

49:50

one would have hoped if one was

49:52

rules. But on the

49:54

other hand, I think there are ways in

49:56

which we can see it's either rules and influence

49:59

in public policy to some extent. Because

50:02

many many people have read a theory of justice

50:05

and have gone into public life

50:08

and gone into service or

50:10

similar roles around the world.

50:13

And I think there's a shift whether it's caused

50:15

by rules or just

50:17

more generally moving away

50:19

from a type of utilitarian maximization

50:23

approach. The idea that what we should do is is

50:25

create the greatest benefit but

50:27

rather think about how policies affect

50:29

the worst off. So in this country,

50:33

political parties right and left.

50:35

Want pay attention, special attention

50:37

to the people who are the least advantaged in

50:40

society. So I see this

50:42

as a slight shift in a Rawls'

50:44

direction. I mean, no one is saying we should make

50:46

the worst off as well off as possible. But

50:50

every party wants to improve the position of

50:52

the worst off even if it's not

50:54

cost effective in utilitarian

50:56

terms. I think we have seen a

50:58

small but significant movement

51:00

there. Well, I suppose one idea that

51:02

hasn't come up yet, but it was absolutely essential

51:05

in thinking, was the idea of democracy.

51:08

We talked about the social contract edition

51:10

and the the idea

51:12

of natural rights, but also,

51:15

in his thinking, especially also as his

51:17

thinking developed later on, thought

51:19

that all we need is a commitment

51:21

to democracy because of key

51:23

feature of democracy is that everyone

51:25

is seen as an equal. So that's we need.

51:27

We don't need more baggage here, theoretical

51:29

baggage in terms of who we are

51:31

as persons is enough that we

51:34

think of our society as committed to democracy

51:36

and to the idea of equality that comes with that.

51:39

Of course, that raises a difficult question today.

51:41

Are we still equally committed to democracy?

51:44

And if

51:44

not, how does that affect the

51:46

chances of sort of project that Rawls'

51:49

are pursued. So are we as

51:51

committed to democracy as Rawls'? Well, as

51:53

well, I think, you know, there there's a lot of

51:55

evidence now, particularly from the United States that

51:58

younger people are not so

52:00

concerned about democracy. And

52:03

given the qualities of the democracies they've

52:05

been experiencing, you can see why disillusion

52:08

may come in. I mean, the Rawls'

52:10

response will be to try to improve democracy

52:12

rather than to to move move

52:15

on. But democracy is very important for

52:17

Rawls', but but it does give a dilemma. There

52:20

was a type of criticism haven't talked

52:22

about that that Rawls' is

52:25

setting out his principles of justice for

52:28

the Just Society. So that raises

52:30

a question about what would democracy

52:33

be doing if rawls has already given us

52:35

the answers? So rawls has told us what

52:37

a just society is. So what are we

52:39

voting about? Now is it is democracy

52:41

just about the most efficient way of achieving

52:44

Rawls' as goals. Well, if so,

52:47

then that does seem rather boring.

52:49

So there was a line of criticism probably from

52:51

the nineteen seventies and eighties. I think

52:54

Benjamin Barber wrote a book called The Conquest

52:56

of Democracy. I think it was quite interesting

52:58

to say that, you know, the goal of the major

53:01

political philosophers is more or less to solve

53:03

problems once and for whereas there's

53:05

a more democratic and says, well, it's changing.

53:07

The issues are changing. Nothing is the

53:09

final answer to anything,

53:12

and so we constantly need to refresh politics.

53:15

So I think we've seen in some interpretations of

53:17

Rawls', both of those ideas, yes, you have a theory

53:19

and you have democracy. And I don't think

53:21

they sit brilliantly well

53:23

together. I've spoken a an

53:26

opposing view to to Joe's

53:28

worry there might be that that actually

53:30

the the importance of democracies.

53:33

They're right at the center of the whole Rawls' project.

53:36

So it's a way of thinking about how do

53:38

you have a set of institutions for free and equal

53:40

people who are going to live together on terms that

53:42

they can all they can all agree

53:44

to. Now, it's gonna be absolutely foundational

53:46

to that, that's going to be a democratic society

53:49

where everyone gets to participate

53:51

in the development of

53:54

that society over time and to think together

53:56

about how it's going to to evolve. And

53:58

so the the kind of democratic protections that

54:00

are built into the first principle of that are very

54:02

sort of central to what rules is still

54:05

thing that's really sort of foundational to its project.

54:07

And I think I mean, in response to

54:09

to Joe's worry, and and, usually, the

54:12

the earrings now have been about you know,

54:14

are we at a point where there's there's a sort of decline

54:16

of confidence in in democracy? There's

54:19

a very interesting discussion of that by the

54:21

American philosopher Tamiel Sheffler from

54:23

New York University where he he has

54:25

a a paper where he talks about the

54:28

Rawls' diagnosis of Donald Trump.

54:30

And the thought there is, well,

54:33

if if liberal democracy looks like

54:35

it's in trouble, is that in some

54:37

way a kind of disprove

54:39

of our best theories of what

54:41

a a just liberal society

54:44

might look like. And Çöpler says, well,

54:46

no, it's really it's really the opposite. What

54:48

Rawls' else gives you is an account of

54:50

what a society in its

54:52

main institutions. I mean, Fabienne was

54:54

was emphasizing, you know, that the idea of basic

54:57

structure, the main institutions of

54:59

your society. What do they owe to the members of

55:01

that society? Well, what

55:03

they owe such Rawls' is something quite quite

55:05

close to his principles. And

55:08

that embodies the sort of attitude of reciprocity.

55:11

You look at your fellow citizens. You look at the

55:13

institutions you live under. And think, yeah,

55:15

I'm being treated here in a kind of reciprocal

55:17

way, and I can affirm my allegiance

55:20

to these institutions because they're realizing something

55:22

really valuable among me and my

55:24

fellow citizens. Now when

55:26

those institutions have broken down

55:28

to to the point where there's

55:30

runaway levels of inequality where

55:33

there's terrible inequality in regard

55:36

to who has political and who

55:38

doesn't. When you're so far away from

55:40

the main commitment to the theory, that

55:42

idea that you're actually living with

55:44

others under turn to let capacity is

55:46

gone. And it's unsurprising then

55:48

in a way that that would lead to a certain kind

55:50

of of disillusioned. So think there's

55:52

there's a a kind of democratic ambition

55:54

in Rawls' for for what's

55:57

valuable about having institutions that

55:59

embody that that idea of

56:01

of people as free and equal living under

56:03

fair and reciprocal terms. And

56:06

and Rawls' a lot of the the pathologies of

56:08

our current societies are

56:10

ones that that really start to happen

56:12

when you move so far away from that that

56:15

kind of ideal of of justice.

56:17

Yeah. Just to to the points

56:19

that Joanne Martin were making that

56:21

indeed Rawls' think that the conundrum

56:24

that Joe raised about

56:26

how is this idea that

56:28

justice is the result of an

56:30

agreement between people

56:32

on the one and well based on democracy really compatible

56:35

with democracy. It was after all democracy is there

56:37

to resolve some of our problems. Right? And I

56:39

would say, yes, the solution here is also to think

56:41

about the principles of justice and applying applying

56:43

to the basic structure of society, but that

56:45

still leaves quite a lot for democracy to decide

56:48

and indeed leaves us a need

56:50

of a vibrant democratic society

56:53

tackle these problems for all sorts of reasons.

56:55

So I do think that's the right

56:57

answer. The level that Rawls'

56:59

thinks of the Principles of Justice applying

57:02

to is as

57:04

if we're about to have a constitutional

57:07

consensus. So these principles

57:09

that are even deeper than the constitution.

57:12

So once we've got the principles, actually,

57:14

there's a lot of work to work out what our

57:16

day to day life would be

57:17

like.

57:17

Do you want to comment So one thing that

57:20

hasn't come up yet in terms of his legacy,

57:22

we were just talking about how

57:24

hugely influential roles the leader of justice

57:26

was within political philosophy and how to

57:28

some extent both became a victim of his own

57:31

success. Right? Because it's successful,

57:33

people pushed back against it. But there's

57:35

further think Rose was also incredibly

57:38

influential through his brilliant

57:40

students. And he this

57:42

influence wasn't just in political philosophy

57:45

even though some of his brilliant students

57:47

were in political philosophy, but others

57:49

were in moral philosophy. And

57:52

one thing that's really remarkable about

57:54

Rose's and students that so many of them

57:56

were women. That is remarkable

57:58

because philosophy is one of those fields

58:00

still now where there aren't a

58:02

lot of women, it's still a field, quite dummy

58:04

nated by men. But

58:07

Rawls' for how however he did

58:09

it managed to have exceptionally successful

58:12

student who were women. So

58:15

in political philosophy, philosophers who

58:17

went on to work sort

58:19

of broadly in the in tradition, but pursuing

58:21

agendas, very much their own were Elizabeth

58:23

Anderson, who worked on equality,

58:26

Michel, Moody Allen Adams, who

58:28

worked on political move women's,

58:30

social justice, including on race.

58:33

And then Jean Hampton, who

58:35

worked on the social contract edition, unfortunately,

58:38

she tried quite early.

58:40

But any moral philosophy, quite

58:43

a large number of rules of student

58:46

developed his sort of kantian ideas.

58:48

I mentioned, Cammed earlier as one of his influences.

58:51

And 4

58:53

like Christine Corsgaard, Barbara Hermann,

58:56

and Anora Neil who's

58:58

was a philosopher at Cambridge. I mean, she's

59:00

still a philosopher who's no longer active at

59:02

Cambridge. They all went on

59:04

to develop the Cancun aspects

59:06

of Rawls' work, again, put

59:09

forward their own mall theories

59:11

and had had a relieved of

59:13

invigorating effect on law of

59:15

philosophy and on banking ethics in particular.

59:18

You spoke to rules. What happened then? Yes.

59:21

And when I had the fortune of being supervised

59:24

by him in my doctoral work when I

59:26

was a visit student at Harvard.

59:28

I was in ninety four, ninety five, and he was

59:30

still active then. And so

59:33

one of the conversations we had concerned

59:35

the impact his theory of justice had

59:38

on American society. And

59:40

it was interesting how to

59:43

see how disappointed that he was. That

59:45

relates back to things both Joe and

59:47

Martin said earlier, not disappointed

59:50

in sort of germanic

59:52

sense why did people not take my fear

59:54

of justice more seriously? But rather,

59:57

he really dedicated his life to

59:59

try and come up with a team of assets that could

1:00:01

be implemented and they thought that precisely

1:00:04

because the initial commitments are so minimal,

1:00:06

all you need is be committed to a democracy

1:00:08

and look what follows, right, an attractive

1:00:10

set of principles of justice. And

1:00:12

yet society, if anything, had

1:00:15

moved further way

1:00:17

from the sort of tendency towards the quality

1:00:19

that we saw after the second world war when

1:00:21

Rawls' started thinking about these

1:00:23

issues. So that was major disappointment

1:00:25

to him, which was, yeah, sad.

1:00:27

Did

1:00:27

you make him think about demanding his theory?

1:00:30

I think it was more hope in the society, but somehow

1:00:32

men

1:00:35

Here's a producer, same as all straight.

1:00:37

Would anyone like to your coffee? Oh,

1:00:40

to your big tea. I'm good. Thank

1:00:42

you. Two

1:00:43

t's, Melvin. Two t's. Thank you very

1:00:45

much. In our time with Melvin

1:00:47

Bragg is produced by Simon Tilletton.

1:00:51

My name is Jonathan Meissen. And two

1:00:53

years ago, we produced Nuremberg, a

1:00:56

dramatized reconstruction of the trial

1:00:58

of the major Nazi war criminals. Their

1:01:01

crimes were indisputable, but one

1:01:03

mystery remained. How did this

1:01:05

group of unremarkable men come

1:01:07

to rule all of Germany? Our

1:01:10

new podcast, Nazis, the

1:01:12

road to power, unravels this

1:01:14

improbable story in sixteen

1:01:16

episodes. Starring Tom Motherstale,

1:01:19

Derek Jacoby, Alexander Vlathos,

1:01:21

Toby Stevens, and Laura Donnelly.

1:01:25

It remains a lesson for us all.

1:01:28

Listen wherever you get your podcasts.

1:01:30

Hello.

1:01:36

My name is Jonathan Mison, and before

1:01:38

you get to your chosen podcast, I want to

1:01:41

ask you one question. How

1:01:43

did an insignificant army corporal?

1:01:45

End up as chancellor of all Germany.

1:01:49

It's a story that's improbable and

1:01:51

also a lesson for us all. My

1:01:54

new podcast, Nazis, The Rotter

1:01:56

Power, unravels it in sixteen

1:01:58

dramatized episodes starring

1:02:01

Tom Middersdale, Derek Jacoby,

1:02:03

Toby Stevens, Alexander Vlahos,

1:02:05

and Laura Donnelly. Listen

1:02:08

wherever you get your podcasts.

Rate

Join Podchaser to...

  • Rate podcasts and episodes
  • Follow podcasts and creators
  • Create podcast and episode lists
  • & much more

Episode Tags

Do you host or manage this podcast?
Claim and edit this page to your liking.
,

Unlock more with Podchaser Pro

  • Audience Insights
  • Contact Information
  • Demographics
  • Charts
  • Sponsor History
  • and More!
Pro Features