Podchaser Logo
Home
Ep46 "Who says you're dead?"

Ep46 "Who says you're dead?"

Released Monday, 12th February 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Ep46 "Who says you're dead?"

Ep46 "Who says you're dead?"

Ep46 "Who says you're dead?"

Ep46 "Who says you're dead?"

Monday, 12th February 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Rate Episode

Episode Transcript

Transcripts are displayed as originally observed. Some content, including advertisements may have changed.

Use Ctrl + F to search

0:05

How do you know when a person is

0:07

dead? I mean, it seems like a straightforward

0:09

problem, but this is often a

0:11

very complex issue, both medically

0:14

and legally, because, as we'll

0:16

see in this episode, death is

0:18

not an event but a process.

0:22

So where do the medical and legal systems

0:24

face off against one another in this question?

0:27

Can a person be declared

0:29

legally dead even though he's very much alive.

0:32

Why in twenty eleven did an

0:35

enormous number of families choose

0:37

to pull their loved ones off life support

0:40

just before the new year? And what does

0:42

this have to do with getting buried alive

0:45

or with your family's religious beliefs,

0:47

or whether someone's head stays alive

0:50

after the guillotine. Welcome

0:55

to Inner Cosmos with me David Eagleman.

0:57

I'm a neuroscientist and author at Stance,

1:00

and in these episodes we sail deeply

1:02

into our three pound universe to understand

1:05

why and how our lives

1:07

look the way they do. Today's

1:19

episode is about the science,

1:21

the ethics, and the questions

1:24

about the end of life, What

1:26

qualifies as death, who

1:28

gets to say that

1:30

you are dead? And what is the future

1:32

of this? Okay,

1:34

so let's start with something that's perhaps

1:37

macabre and unexpected. But

1:39

if you're a modern adult and you die

1:42

suddenly, you have all these bill

1:44

pay and credit card payments and automatic

1:47

withdrawals that are scheduled, and

1:49

your finances might keep on trucking

1:51

for a while. You may even receive

1:53

some auto deposits into your bank account,

1:55

And with all the comings and goings,

1:58

it would look to someone who didn't know that

2:00

you're still making transactions. And

2:02

if you happened to have some pre

2:05

scheduled emails that you'd previously

2:07

written, those might go out, and various

2:09

legal things get triggered at different points,

2:11

and it will probably look for a little while

2:14

like you're still making stuff happen

2:16

in the world. And I was thinking

2:18

about this the other day as an analogy

2:21

to what happens with your biology.

2:24

Generally speaking, death is declared

2:27

when a heart stops beating and

2:30

or someone stops breathing. But

2:32

even though we think about death like a binary

2:35

event, there's no central

2:37

command center in the body that says,

2:40

okay, now we're done. Everyone stop

2:42

working. Because the body is made

2:44

of literally trillions of cells,

2:47

and all of their chemical signals

2:50

are connected and intricate cascades

2:52

and loops and when something stops

2:55

running, these nested feedback

2:57

loops tend to bump things

2:59

back to the normal range. We have this compensation.

3:03

Now, at some point the whole show

3:06

grinds to a halt. The compensatory

3:08

mechanisms can't keep up

3:11

with the catastrophic failure of

3:14

loop after loop that stops working,

3:16

and eventually the whole system stops.

3:18

But death is not a moment

3:20

in time. It is a process. In

3:23

other words, the individual cells

3:26

don't necessarily know that the heart

3:28

has stopped or the brain has

3:30

stopped its cognitive whirlwind

3:32

of activity, so they just keep trucking

3:35

along for as long as they can. So

3:38

here's an analogy so we can think about this.

3:40

Imagine you are a space

3:42

alien that's looking down on the Earth and

3:47

you see a large blobby

3:49

organism moving towards some

3:51

fortress. And then the

3:54

blobby organism extends two

3:56

arms around the fortress and starts

3:58

to squeeze it. But then some explosions

4:01

go off and the organism stops moving.

4:03

It seems to die. But then

4:05

you use your alien telescope

4:08

to zoom in more closely, and for the first time,

4:11

you notice a single warrior

4:13

running up the hill, turning back swinging

4:16

his sword, falling to his knees

4:18

in lamentations, and regaining his

4:20

footing and running towards the fortress again.

4:23

So you start panning your telescope round

4:25

and you notice a dozen of these

4:28

rogue swordsmen in different locations

4:30

around the battlefield. And that's when you realize

4:33

that the blobby organism who

4:35

came upon the fortress was actually

4:37

composed of lots of little

4:40

individual agents, all of

4:42

whom worked in concert

4:44

and maybe had hierarchies and rules

4:46

of engagement and backup plans such

4:48

that even when most of the army

4:51

was killed, that didn't necessitate

4:53

that every part stopped the

4:56

survival of individual

4:58

warriors. Suddenly, rev feels that

5:00

the blob was made of these little

5:02

swordsmen all along, even though that was

5:04

difficult to see. And this

5:06

is what happens biologically.

5:09

We are made up of cells that

5:11

operate together. This is

5:13

what makes a person or any animal.

5:16

Trillions of cells collaborating

5:19

to make this giant creature that

5:21

moves around and finds other

5:23

collections of cells to eat and take

5:25

their energy. And researchers

5:28

have made recent discoveries about cells

5:30

that stay alive and actually get more

5:33

active well after

5:35

the rest of the body has been declared

5:37

dead. In other words, these little swordsmen

5:40

warriors that are still running around

5:42

even after the blob has

5:44

stopped. For example, some

5:47

researchers at University of Illinois Chicago

5:49

looked at little pieces of fresh

5:52

brain that get removed during

5:54

brain surgery, and they looked at these either

5:57

right when the tissue was removed or

5:59

at different times after the removal.

6:02

So they called this a simulated

6:04

death experiment, and their point was to think about

6:06

what happens when tissue gets

6:09

separated and dies. And

6:11

what they found after the tissue is removed

6:14

is that some brain cells actually

6:16

increase their activity. These cells will

6:18

often grow really large and they sprout

6:21

long finger like processes for

6:23

several hours after death. Now,

6:26

in some sense this is not too surprising, because

6:28

these are glial cells in

6:30

the brain whose job is to take

6:32

care of inflammation. But

6:35

the researchers pointed out that most

6:37

people don't even look at the brain after

6:39

death because they assume that everything

6:41

dies. But in fact, eighty

6:43

percent of the genes being expressed

6:46

kept on being expressed at their normal

6:48

levels. Twenty four hours later.

6:51

A few genes had their expression levels

6:53

go down, but there was a third group

6:55

of genes, which they called zombie

6:57

genes, whose activity went up,

7:00

and as a result, you have all these cells

7:03

still running around and doing stuff.

7:06

And if we zoom out our camera, we find

7:08

that different organs keep functioning

7:10

for different amounts of time. So, for example,

7:13

at some point we would say the brain

7:15

is dead. That's followed a little

7:18

later by the heart. Then the liver

7:20

dies next, then the kidneys

7:22

and pancreas can last another hour past

7:24

that before they die, and other

7:26

parts of your body like your heart

7:29

valves, and the corneas of your eyes

7:31

and your tendons and your skin that's

7:34

still alive after about a day.

7:36

So the idea that everything stops

7:39

when you die is not correct.

7:41

Returning to the space alien analogy, imagine

7:44

that the medics come in to take care of the

7:46

fallen warriors, and so there's still lots

7:49

of activity even after the main

7:51

army has fallen. But

7:53

it gets even weirder when we talk about

7:55

things that the larger level

7:57

of the creature. And there's been a history

8:00

of asking these questions. For example,

8:03

you might think that death

8:05

is really clear if say

8:07

a person has had their head cut off

8:09

with a guillotine, I'm going to dive

8:11

into that issue in a future episode because

8:13

the whole thing is so wacky

8:16

and fascinating. But I'll just mention now

8:18

that in the eighteen hundreds, when the guillotine

8:21

was very popular, people got

8:23

interested in this question of whether the head

8:25

can stay conscious after

8:27

separation from the body, and what they

8:29

would do is pick up the freshly

8:32

severed head and try to get it

8:34

to talk or at least blink its eyes

8:37

on command. And at

8:39

that time, other scientists were trying

8:41

things like taking a decapitated

8:44

head from a German shepherd dog

8:46

and reattaching it to the blood supply

8:48

of another dog to see if simply

8:51

restoring blood flow through the brain was

8:54

enough to restore its function. So

8:57

stay tuned for that episode. But what these experiment

9:00

it's highlight is that this question of

9:02

where to draw the line between

9:04

life and death has been with us a

9:06

long time, and in modern

9:08

times we have things like the field

9:10

of cryogenics, which is the art

9:13

of freezing a body

9:15

after death, so it has a chance

9:18

of being revived by future

9:20

scientists who might know how to do

9:22

that, even though we don't know now. In

9:24

the field of cryogenics, it's popular

9:27

to sometimes just save the head

9:29

and get rid of the body, and the assumption

9:31

or the hope really is that that can

9:34

be sufficient, and that if you

9:36

are maintained at ninety six

9:38

degrees below freezing, then you're not actually

9:41

dead, but you're in a state of suspended

9:43

animation and can eventually

9:46

be rebooted. So

9:49

why does all this matter, this question of where

9:51

to draw the line between life and

9:53

death. Well, first of all, it matters

9:55

for the medical system, and

9:57

we see cases come up all the time in hot

10:00

hospitals where there is confusion

10:02

or disagreement about how to make

10:05

the call. There was a case

10:07

in Texas where the doctors told

10:09

a man that his son, who had

10:11

been in a coma, would never return

10:14

back to consciousness, and so the doctors

10:16

wanted to make the call to remove

10:18

the young man from life support, and

10:20

the father was so distraught

10:23

that he pulled a gun on the doctors

10:25

and medical staff and wouldn't let

10:27

them near his son in the hospital bed,

10:29

And so the police were immediately dispatched

10:32

and this man was arrested and put in jail

10:34

for eleven months. But incredibly,

10:37

the son enjoyed a full recovery

10:40

and once the father was released from

10:42

jail. The two of them were happily

10:45

reunited. All of this points

10:47

to the difficulty in determining

10:49

when a body has died irreversibly,

10:53

and the question of life and death matters

10:56

enormously for legal systems

10:58

because so much pivots on whether

11:00

a person is considered alive or

11:03

dead in the eyes of the law.

11:05

How do we know when that line has

11:07

been crossed? So there

11:09

are so many fascinating medical

11:12

and legal and ethical issues around deciding

11:15

when a person has died, and those

11:17

viewpoints don't always align,

11:20

and perhaps surprisingly they often conflict

11:22

badly. And add to this particular

11:26

religious practices that people have and

11:29

business issues like tax implications,

11:31

and what you have is a fascinating set

11:34

of questions that arise. So

11:36

that's what I want to talk about today. How

11:38

we as a society make that

11:40

call and how should we so

11:43

To dig into this, I called up my

11:45

friend and colleague, Jacob Appel. Now,

11:48

Jacob is a very accomplished thinker and

11:50

writer and man of many talents.

11:52

He has seven graduate degrees,

11:55

but for today's episode, the two

11:57

most salient are his law

11:59

degree from Harvard and his medical

12:02

degree from Columbia. Jacob

12:04

works as an emergency room psychiatrist

12:06

in the Mount Sinai Health System, and

12:08

he also serves as the director of Ethics

12:11

Education. So I called

12:13

him up to talk with him about the question

12:16

of how we as a society should

12:18

think about making the tough calls

12:21

about whether a person should be declared

12:23

dead or not, and the complexities

12:26

that lurk inside that seemingly

12:28

simple question, complexities

12:31

that are scientific and legal

12:33

and cultural. How

12:38

do the medical and the legal systems decide

12:41

when you are dead?

12:44

Well, it's interesting because the medical and legal systems

12:46

have very different histories and very different

12:48

approaches. As a legal concept,

12:51

being dead has significant implications

12:53

not just for you, but for your loved ones and

12:56

for society. So, for example, if you're

12:58

dead, your spouse can re marry,

13:01

your heirrors can inherit, You

13:03

stop getting social Security. So,

13:05

whatever your biological status, if you're declared

13:08

dead, it can have significant implications for the.

13:10

World and for you as well.

13:11

I'm reminded several years ago

13:14

a man from Romania had gone to work

13:16

in Turkey, and he'd been gone

13:18

for a long time.

13:19

His wife couldn't find him.

13:20

She had him legally declared dead, and then

13:22

he came back as a surprise,

13:25

and he couldn't run an apartment or get a job his

13:27

casement all the way to the Romanian Supreme

13:29

Court because he was legally dead and nobody,

13:31

even though he was standing in front of him, would overrule

13:34

us. And I will mention also legally

13:36

there are these gray areas. So for example,

13:38

if you were lost to see historically, how

13:41

did we know how long you had it be gone before

13:43

you were dead? And there were different rules

13:45

for how much time had it passed before they could

13:47

give away your property versus not

13:50

having rights over your children.

13:51

So you can be dead for one purpose and alive for another.

13:54

Wasn't there some sixteenth century French

13:57

soldier that this happened to last

13:59

name Gear?

14:01

Yeah, there's a great movie, The Return

14:03

of Martin Gear, which is a classic

14:05

case of this, where someone allegedly

14:08

I believe it was in one hundred Years War, came

14:11

back after being lost in battle. It turned out

14:13

he actually wasn't the person who claimed he

14:15

was. But there were a number of famous cases

14:17

like this over the years, and as a famous

14:19

poem by Tennyson about

14:22

Enoch Arden, hence the term that

14:24

has come into the English language Enoch Arden laws

14:26

which the laws would refer to how long you have

14:28

to be missing before you're dead.

14:30

Wow. Okay, So from

14:33

the legal point of view, there are all these

14:35

things to be considered, including, for example,

14:38

tax laws. Can you just

14:40

mention what happened between the two nine and

14:42

twenty eleven?

14:44

Oh?

14:44

Absolutely, So the Bush

14:46

administration had enacted tax laws

14:49

that gave people a significant tax break on

14:51

their inheritance, and they were going to

14:53

expire at some point, and people's inheritance taxes

14:56

would go up substantially as a

14:58

result of which many people who were at the end of life life

15:00

on life support or their families want

15:02

at their life support terminated before

15:04

January first, when their taxes would double.

15:07

At an entire boutique corner

15:09

of a major New.

15:10

York City law firm is actually devoted specifically

15:12

to this practice.

15:14

Right, So, somebody was on life support

15:17

and the adult children would

15:19

say, look, it's December, let's

15:22

go ahead and pull this now so

15:24

that he dies before January first.

15:27

Yeah, they would say, Grandpa would much

15:29

rather die on December thirtieth and

15:31

leave one hundred billion dollars to his

15:33

grandkids than die on January

15:35

second. Still unloose it. Two days

15:37

later, and leave them nothing. And honestly,

15:39

I can't argue with that.

15:41

Yeah, So how do hospital

15:44

ethics boards deal with questions

15:46

like that? Sure?

15:48

Are so most decisions in hospitals or

15:50

recommendations, you're done by committee. So

15:52

you have an ethics committee, You have a consultant who

15:54

actually gathers the information and presents it to

15:56

the committee, which consist of experts

15:58

in a range of different fields, so not

16:01

just medicine, surgery, pediatrics, but social

16:03

work, nursing, the hospital chaplain.

16:06

They sort of build a consensus and then

16:08

obviously, if you can't build a consensus

16:10

or can't get the family on board, then cases

16:13

end up going to court, and ultimately, in cases

16:15

like this, the court usually will decide looking

16:17

at all the evidence brought before them.

16:19

Okay, and so there are all these legal

16:21

considerations, what are the medical considerations

16:24

when we think about what is death?

16:26

Sure, and the medical considerations are actually

16:29

just as complex. In

16:31

an earlier era, you probably

16:33

have seen movies like The Cursed

16:35

Living Dead, where people are believed dead and then they

16:38

come back to life suddenly, and people who are afraid of

16:40

being buried alive.

16:41

It was actually a fairly.

16:44

Ineffective diagnostic tool to be certain

16:47

someone was dead, they would do things like hold

16:49

up a mirror to your mouth and see if there was

16:51

actually vapor on it, to see if you were breathing.

16:53

So they made mistakes.

16:56

So actually this actually happened

16:58

where people were buried alive.

17:00

Yes, I mean it wasn't a common occurrence,

17:02

but it did happen. I will add,

17:05

as strangers who may sound it still

17:07

happens occasionally. Today you hear these

17:09

stories about people who show up in the morgue

17:11

or show up in a funeral home and

17:14

suddenly they wake up. Usually, I

17:16

will add, by the way, those people are still in a very bad

17:18

shape and they don't make it in the long run. I

17:20

don't know of any case to people who have actually been

17:23

to the morgue and then got home and good health.

17:25

But people have gone and they started breathing and ended

17:27

up backing the ice you before, So that

17:29

should give us pause.

17:31

How does that happen currently? Is it in

17:33

areas where there's not good medical

17:36

diagnosis of what has happened?

17:40

I wouldn't be that critical.

17:41

I would say it's a very hard There are a whole bunch of different

17:43

tests for determining whether someone is dead. Now

17:46

and different diagnostic tools and doctors

17:48

do their best. And sometimes if you're barely

17:51

breathing, and if your pulses very sporadic

17:53

and they catch you a couple of times at the wrong moment,

17:56

maybe you get unlucky.

17:57

I will add often this.

17:58

Does occur in the developing world, where maybe

18:00

their diagnostic tools are not as strong. I

18:03

don't know of any cases in New York City with my luck,

18:05

I'll be the first.

18:08

Okay, So back to a few decades

18:10

ago or a century ago. So you hold

18:12

a mirror to the mouth and you see if there's

18:14

fog on the mirror, and then

18:16

what happened.

18:18

So eventually we did no enough about anatomy

18:20

to recognize cardiac and pulmonary death. Cardiopulmonary

18:23

death, you stop breathing and you

18:25

don't get a pulse for a propracted period

18:27

of time, we accept that you're dead.

18:29

Like how long? What's a protracted period?

18:32

That depended on the doctor.

18:35

Honestly, if you're not breathing or

18:37

you know, a pulse for a good ten to fifteen minutes,

18:39

the odds of you reviving naturally on your own get

18:41

pretty darn low. When you get much

18:43

past that, your odds for surviving

18:46

in a way that is meaningfully cognitive or

18:48

very low and most people stop at some point,

18:50

stop crying. But that was the diagnostic tool

18:53

back then. I will add, by the way,

18:55

that most people historically back then

18:57

were in very bad shape by the time they reached that pointing.

18:59

It's been other death bed for hours or

19:01

days or weeks.

19:03

So what happened next?

19:05

So there were technological developments

19:07

in medical science that allowed

19:09

us to check for cardiopulmonary

19:11

death basically to figure out whether or not

19:13

your heart was still beating, whether your lungs

19:16

were still breathing, And that was the test

19:18

for many, many years until the nineteen sixties.

19:20

And if you stop breathing and if your

19:22

heartstep beating, you were dead. And

19:24

that, I will add, by the way, is the test still

19:27

used in some religious communities, in some cultural

19:29

traditions. Starting

19:31

in the late nineteen sixties with the

19:34

advent of organ transplant,

19:37

which meant there was a need to harvest organs

19:39

or procure organs from the individuals

19:42

as quickly as possible, and the

19:44

rise of artificial ventilation and

19:47

later artificial heart support, which

19:49

meant that people could be kept alive for months

19:52

or even a year or two on a respirat or

19:54

on a ventilator. That

19:56

created the challenge of how did we know when these individuals

19:58

were dead? And there was a debate

20:00

over whether brain death should be acceptable,

20:03

and the ultimate decision was made by a

20:05

committee of experts at Harvard that has been

20:07

adopted widely that whole

20:09

brain death would be the standard. So, if

20:11

you have two flat EEGs, your

20:14

brain stops functioning entirely, you

20:16

are now legally dead in every state. I

20:19

will add New Jersey, and

20:22

to a lesser degree under some circumstances.

20:24

New York allows people with a religious

20:26

belief only in cardiopulmonary death to opt

20:28

out of that standard, but other states do

20:30

not.

20:31

So give me an example of having

20:33

a religious belief and how that might change

20:36

the decision that a family makes.

20:38

Sure.

20:39

So let us say that my grandfather

20:41

is on a ventilator

20:44

which is artificial. One support and intet

20:46

to buy that which is a machimee that for a

20:48

short period of time to fairly

20:50

late the period of time. Now with new technology can

20:53

replace the heart, so it's entirely artificial.

20:55

And yet he has two flat

20:57

egs. His brain

21:00

is showing no function at all. In

21:02

New Jersey. If I have a religious tradition

21:05

that says that only cardiopulmonary

21:07

depth is alive. In theory, I could

21:10

raise the funds to bring that individual

21:12

home to my living room and keep them on

21:14

ventilator support and buy bad support until

21:16

they can no longer support their

21:19

cart and lungs with those machines, which could

21:21

be a year.

21:23

And this happens sometimes right where someone takes

21:25

a person home.

21:28

It is rare, but it has happened.

21:31

I believe there was a famous case in Utah, a

21:33

Jesse Kutchin case where it has happened. In

21:35

addition to which there have been cases where people

21:38

the Johi McMath case may be the most known,

21:40

who were what was presumed to be a

21:43

state of brain depth for

21:45

families who do not accept that definition, who

21:47

brought their relatives to New Jersey to

21:49

then replace the facilities that keep people who are

21:52

alive in a cardiopulmonary manner but

21:54

is ceased by the brain death standard alive.

21:57

And what's the reason that people do this. It's because

22:00

their religioustration tells them

22:03

even though they're on a bivalve

22:05

and there on a ventilator, they

22:08

do they think the person could come back, or they have other

22:10

issues. I know you wrote once about somebody's

22:14

belief in reincarnation and how that affected.

22:17

So there are two different categories of people, and

22:19

we might treat the cases the same way or

22:21

differently.

22:22

There are those.

22:23

Individuals who truly

22:25

believe that their relative is going to revive themselves,

22:28

even though the data, overwhelmingly

22:30

from past practice says that's not going to happen,

22:33

and they're hoping for a miracle.

22:34

So to speak.

22:35

There are other individuals who may say,

22:38

you know, I understand that my grandfather

22:40

isn't really going to wake up again, but either

22:43

I, or more appropriately,

22:45

he had a deep religious belief that it was

22:47

important to die of quote unquote natural

22:49

causes or if you believe in reincarnation,

22:52

to die at a certain time, and I

22:54

want to fulfill his wish, even though

22:56

I understand that by your standard he's dead. By

22:58

a religious standard of our book, our

23:00

Bible, or tradition, he's not dead, and

23:02

I want to wait the process out.

23:04

I'll add one more thought on that it's okay,

23:06

which.

23:07

Is you also might want to ask the question, does it matter

23:09

whether if someone's been declared brain dead

23:12

you're willing to pay for it when you take them home,

23:14

whether you're asking the taxpayers to put the bill for

23:16

it, because then the vast majority

23:19

of us would say, the taxpayers are paying to

23:21

keep a dead person on a life

23:23

support system in your living room. And the other

23:25

thing to think about is there's something inappropriate

23:27

or grotesque about it. If

23:29

I were to want to bring my grandmother home embalmed

23:32

like Lenin on display in his tomb and prop

23:35

work in my living room, our society would not let

23:37

me do that, not just for public health reasons,

23:39

but probably for reasons of what we would call

23:41

common decency or horem or appropriateness.

23:44

Some would argue, this is not that different.

23:46

And how does this work in terms of making decisions

23:49

for somebody else. Let's say that somebody

23:51

is in critical condition. It doesn't look likely they'll

23:53

recover, but maybe there's some extreme measures

23:56

you can take that involve amputations

23:58

and other things, and a decision

24:01

has to be made about whether that person

24:03

would want that kind of heroic

24:06

medical treatment with the possible

24:08

consequences. How

24:11

does a hospital make the decision about

24:13

that?

24:14

So, while there is some variation among

24:17

state laws, the general accepted

24:19

principle in this country is that we use a substituted

24:21

judgment or vicarious judgment standard,

24:24

which if we asked, what would this person would

24:26

have wanted if they were still awake

24:28

and lucid and able to express an opinion. The

24:31

only two groups of people we don't use that approach

24:33

for are children, where

24:36

parents can decide based on what they perceive

24:38

to be the best interest within certain societal

24:40

parameters, and people who've never

24:42

had the capacity or ability to make that decision.

24:45

We view it as too far elite to say you

24:47

were born with a such a significant cognitive impairment

24:49

that you could never understand his question. But

24:51

if you hadn't been bored in that way, what would

24:53

you want to have had done.

24:55

I've actually been critical of that latter approach.

24:57

Because in that situation we use a societal

25:00

best interest standard, what society would

25:02

think is in your best interests. I have argued

25:04

that for certain communities, let's say you're

25:06

an Amish, Mennonite or a Casidic

25:09

Jew, it might be more appropriate to ask

25:11

what would be the best interest standard in your community,

25:14

because it doesn't seem too far a bridge

25:16

for me to say, if you were born a Mennonite,

25:18

you would want what a Menonite tradition speaks to not

25:21

be overall societal standard.

25:24

Tell me about what happened during Hurricane

25:26

Katrina with the ventilators and what

25:28

that means.

25:30

Sure, so, I think during Hurricane Katrina

25:33

there was a medical

25:35

crisis where they had patients who were ventilators

25:38

who needed them to stay alive, and

25:41

a number of questions around end of life arose. One

25:43

the medical teams for safety had

25:45

to leave some of these patients. Some of them could not be evacuated,

25:48

and they had to decide whether or not to

25:51

continue them on life support, whether or

25:53

not to use morphine

25:55

or other techniques to ease their suffering that

25:57

could have the risk of death. Into

26:00

trial, there was a doctor Poe was actually put on trial

26:02

and eventually acquitted for her role in this.

26:04

These were not easy.

26:05

Questions, right, because

26:07

the decision she made was, you know, if

26:09

we are going to run out of power, then

26:12

people will suffer if they don't have the

26:14

ventilator on anymore, and so

26:17

do we pull the plug

26:19

before we run out of power? Was

26:21

that the issue?

26:23

I mean, that was what she was accused

26:25

of doing. As she describes it.

26:28

I believe she would say she was giving people

26:30

morphine or other medication with a dual

26:32

intent that might have ended their

26:34

life as a result, but the primary goal was

26:36

to ease their suffering. And in palliative

26:39

care and end of life decision making, we often do

26:41

recognize this concept of dual intent.

26:43

We may intend to do one thing that inadvertently

26:46

is a different consequence, but intending

26:48

to relieve suffering that leads to death,

26:50

we view conceptually is very different from intending

26:52

to cause death.

27:10

Okay, so the way we make decisions about

27:12

death now has to do in

27:15

part with this concept of irreversibility.

27:18

And my question to you is how

27:20

do you think about this in terms of the new

27:22

technologies that are coming along and

27:26

change that definition of irreversibility.

27:31

I mean, this comes up not just with defining

27:33

death, but an all end of life decision

27:35

making. So people

27:38

may be toward the end of life

27:40

and have what we call it terminal prognosis, but

27:43

there's no way to be certain that a new technology

27:45

will develop that can cure their illness. And there have been

27:47

cases now of people with rare

27:49

cancers that seemed to one hundred percent fatal

27:52

they always had been before, where new immunotherapies

27:55

suddenly appear in the market or emerge

27:57

as experimental treatments that then save their lives.

28:00

And who are we to.

28:01

Take away someone's hope, which is why we generally

28:03

defer to what the patient's wishes are. And

28:06

that also creates an economic challenge,

28:08

because we may know society that

28:10

almost everyone in this situation dies, or

28:12

even that so far everybody has. But who

28:14

are we to take away hope from the veryous one number

28:17

of people who want to be the teals,

28:19

so to speak, and not the bell.

28:21

I can give you a very concrete example of this.

28:23

I don't know if it's still true, but there was a time

28:26

when if you went on the internet, let's say you were diagnosed

28:28

with ALS blue garage disease and

28:30

typed in prognosis ALS

28:33

blue garage disease on Google, the first

28:35

picture that came up was not lou Garage.

28:37

It was Stephen Hawking.

28:39

The physicists who lived I'm guessing

28:41

thirty forty years with the illness, even

28:44

though the vast majority of people died.

28:46

Within a few years.

28:47

And once you see that, it's hard to make any

28:49

meaning out of statements like a certain percentage

28:51

of Medicare or Medicaid dollars are spent in

28:53

a certain period toward the end of life, because

28:56

as I always ask the medical students after I explain

28:59

that, I say, if if you're in the last six months of

29:01

life, raise your hand now.

29:03

And obviously we don't know.

29:05

So Jacob, when you think about the question

29:07

of irreversibility, what do you think about cryogenics?

29:11

So I'm not one who can say that cryogenics

29:14

will never work, though my guess is there will

29:16

be other technologies that will be developed beforehand

29:19

that may be far more effective at

29:21

life lengthening, or life preserving, or

29:23

even reversibility. I can say

29:26

that nothing I have seen suggests that criogenics

29:28

as it works now is very effective.

29:30

I would not suggest having your head caught off

29:32

now in storage somewhere.

29:34

What else are you seeing that seems like it could

29:37

be more effective?

29:39

I mean, I think at some point, and this is

29:41

obviously in a far fetched way, many

29:43

many years in the future, we may be

29:45

able to download people's personality,

29:48

download their brands into some kind of system

29:51

A computer might be too simplistical word,

29:53

but some kind of extra intelligence

29:55

system that can then reprogram individualism

29:58

in a way That is not something I would say that

30:00

you should bank on in your lifetime or mind. I

30:02

think we're far better off focusing on technologies

30:05

that can extend human life as it exists

30:07

now. And I will add

30:09

even beyond that, we may ultimately have

30:11

that technology to transfer heads

30:14

from one individual or a brand from individual

30:16

into bodies of another, but again we are nowhere

30:18

near prime time on that. I know there's an

30:20

Italian sturage, and thinking about doing that, I

30:23

would be very reluctant to try that procedure

30:25

because not only the possibility will work, which

30:27

the possibility, what would suffer immensely during

30:29

the process.

30:31

I think maybe it was Paul Broca.

30:34

Somebody actually did this with German shepherd

30:36

dogs, where they cut off one head and attached

30:38

to the vasculature to the heart

30:41

of another dog and kept the

30:43

head alive that way.

30:46

I'm not sure if it always broke up, but a number

30:48

of different people have done this over the years,

30:50

with more or less suctatistic with various

30:52

animals, So the theoretical

30:55

concept is there. There obviously are

30:57

both a number of logistical premises

31:00

is in terms of attaching neurop tissue, and

31:02

also a large number of ethical dilemmas.

31:05

It's very I don't want to say easy, but

31:07

it's much more easy to get decided to accept killing

31:09

a German shepherd to say of another German shepherd.

31:12

They get used to kill one person to say of another

31:14

person.

31:15

That's right, Although as I as I understand

31:17

it, it's the idea is taking

31:20

somebody who is brain dead

31:22

but their body is still functioning, and

31:24

then taking somebody else who has

31:26

a functioning brain. But let's say they're quadriplegic

31:29

and their body is degrading. So it's

31:31

somebody who is already judged

31:33

to be dead by brain dead standards.

31:36

Is the first body?

31:39

Absolutely, I mean that that is the

31:41

theoretical approach. The

31:43

obviously both logistical

31:45

challenges in terms of what if you have a mismatch

31:48

of heads and bodies, and the

31:50

ethical questions of who this person legally

31:52

is going forward and how they relate to their

31:55

one family versus the other inheritance

31:58

whose fingerprints to the have in a legal sense

32:01

becomes very very complicated, very very

32:03

quickly. I'm not saying this issue can't be solved.

32:06

I would say we want to solve these questions

32:08

before we start using the technology, or

32:10

we're going to find yourself painted into a very unpleasant

32:12

quarter.

32:14

Yes, So let me come back to that question about

32:17

how committees at

32:19

hospitals, how ethics committees make this decision.

32:21

You pointed out that ethics committees are

32:23

made up of many different points of view.

32:27

What have you seen is the most contentious

32:31

argument that you have come across.

32:34

I can tell you that speaking more broadly,

32:36

because I don't want to reveal now Sini's confidential

32:38

epics debates, but historically the

32:41

most controversial issue in epics committees

32:44

has related to a very specific scenario that

32:46

occurred over and over again throughout this country

32:48

from nineteen seventies through the nineteen nineties, and

32:51

how to do with patients who were

32:53

in accidents with C three S force

32:55

bibal fractures so they would never be

32:58

able to breathe again on their own, never be able to

33:00

to move below their neck on their own, and they would

33:02

wake up from his accidents and say, I

33:04

don't want to live like this, turn my life support

33:06

off, and palliative care

33:08

would say we need to respect their autonomous

33:11

wishes. They don't want to suffer. And psychiatry

33:13

would say, but we know that

33:16

a certain percentage of people, approximately half

33:19

who we do talk into staying alive

33:21

and do therapy with after a year are

33:23

actually glad they stayed

33:26

alive and take meaningful value in their life. And they point

33:28

out, for example, the Superman actor Christopher

33:30

Reeve and Pallid of Care would cut back and

33:32

say, yes, but we know that the other half or

33:34

not, and the interest to the other half

33:36

to not suffer existentially outweigh

33:38

those of the first half to have a

33:40

meaningful life in the long run. And this was a deeply

33:43

heated debate which there's no conceptually

33:45

correct answer. You can't reduce

33:48

it to any level where there's a right answer. I

33:50

can tell you in practice, palliad of care

33:52

has won misbattle.

33:54

Ah And what was it with Christopher

33:56

Reeve? Which way did

33:58

he go on that he was happy that he had stay

34:00

alive.

34:01

After a year?

34:01

Even I think before a year he'd was very grateful to have

34:04

stayed live and he brought great meaning to his life

34:06

and helped others. But I will add, if

34:08

you're Superman and you have a loving

34:10

family and a great deal of financials

34:13

for it and amazing doctors, it may be

34:15

easier to find that comfort zone than

34:17

if you're indigent. If you don't have social

34:19

support if you don't have good medical care, if you're

34:22

in a back room somewhere in a nursing facility.

34:24

So I think the other major issue that is

34:26

the end of life, which we've only touched

34:28

on the iceberg tip of the iceberg up

34:31

so far. He is medical aid and dying,

34:33

which has become a national debate over

34:35

when, if ever, people can choose to end their own lives.

34:38

And there's a slow consensus building that

34:40

people with terminal illness, terminal physical

34:42

illness should be able to end their own lives

34:45

if they have a diagnosis of als

34:48

or cancer and they're not going to survive a prolonged period

34:50

of time. And we've seen from one state,

34:52

Oregon in the nineteen nineties to I believe it's now

34:54

ten jurisdictions to legalize this, and

34:56

the trend going forward is to expand this. However,

34:59

we have really not come to terms with

35:01

a question of people who are not suffering

35:04

physically but suffering psychiatrically

35:07

or existentially. And

35:10

for example, we've seen this heated debate in Colorado

35:12

over patients with anarettia who have

35:14

not responded to treatment over a very long period of

35:16

time should be able to turn down refeeding

35:19

or turn down nutritional

35:22

support, even if it means the end of their life, and the

35:24

way we would let a patient with a kidney

35:26

problem turn down dialysis let themselves

35:28

die.

35:29

And we're going to see this question more and more.

35:31

Obviously, if you show up in the emergency room and

35:34

you've broken up with your prom date and you take

35:36

it over as a tile and all, I don't think any Risgilble

35:38

person would say, well, you've had a long, meaningful life,

35:40

you should be able to make this decision. On the other

35:42

head, if you've had depression for

35:44

forty years and you've suffered and no

35:47

treatment is worked after every intervention and

35:49

you say, if you could help me, I want

35:51

that, But since you can't, please let me in my life.

35:54

It's a harder question.

35:56

And why do you see these questions coming

35:58

up more and more?

36:00

Well, I think they've come up in part because

36:02

patients are raising these issues and the clinical

36:04

practice. Patients often will say, doctor,

36:07

I've done everything you've asked me to do. I'm

36:09

in that very small percentage of people who simply

36:11

don't respond to treatment, whether it's for psychosis

36:15

or for depression or for anxiety. I

36:17

wish I did but I've waited you out

36:20

for forty years and there hasn't been a new technology.

36:22

I don't want to wait any longer. And

36:25

you've actually seen a handful of countries, Canada

36:27

most recently, adopt legalization.

36:31

And so what do hospital ethics committees

36:33

decide on these or is it just

36:36

a very contentious issue or people disagree?

36:39

Well, it's not yet a contentious issue in the United States,

36:41

because no American state lets you make this

36:43

choice yet. But I imagine now that Canada

36:46

and several European countries have changed their rules

36:48

in the last year or two, we're going to see

36:51

at least debate over this coming forward.

36:52

In the United States.

36:53

I were to hear colleges discussing this and

36:55

this widespread disagreement.

36:58

So what's going on in the United States? Is

37:01

medical assistant suicide for someone

37:03

who is physically ill,

37:05

right, but not mentally exactly? Okay?

37:07

Yeah, and I will add in all the cases in

37:09

the United States, we do not have a

37:11

euphenagia program. We do not end

37:13

someone's life if they can't make the choice on their own. We

37:16

only have a program where we will prescribe your medication

37:18

to let you choose death. When the time comes. In

37:21

my own experience, having talked to many patients,

37:24

and this may surprise people, be people who benefit

37:26

from this option the most are people who never

37:29

use it and people who know that if

37:31

things got bad enough, they could

37:33

make this choice, which actually gives them

37:35

hope to keep on fighting their illness. It's

37:37

paradoxical, but it's really a stunning

37:40

phenomena, fascinating.

37:43

How does it work? Sorry, so they're prescribed

37:46

the medication that are actually given them, medication

37:48

where they can pull the ripcord if they want

37:51

to. Is that the idea?

37:53

Yeah, So a doctor will write you a prescription and

37:55

you fill the prescription after a number

37:57

of safeguards, an interview with a psychiatrist. I

37:59

mean, you can choose whether to take this medication

38:01

that will end your life in a very peaceful way. In

38:03

some states people actually have going away parties,

38:05

so to speak, where they bring their friends and family,

38:08

which is not that different from how death was

38:10

in the nineteenth century, when people often

38:13

had diseases that were terminal, where they would

38:15

be on a deathbed and their friends and family would come to

38:17

say goodbye. Now we've sanitized

38:19

death in a way. People die in hospitals.

38:22

I think as a medical resident, the most

38:24

disconcerting experience ever was

38:27

showing up in a hospital room at five in the morning,

38:29

six in the morning to see a patient you've seen the night before,

38:32

and finding the room empty, which the patient

38:34

had passed away overnight and completely sanitized

38:36

and stripped down, like a hotel room where sometimes

38:39

even they already brought the next patient into the bed,

38:41

which are very different and in some ways dehumanizing

38:44

process. I understand why that

38:46

may be necessary with the economic forces in

38:48

medicine right now, better than having

38:50

the living person waiting on a gurning

38:52

and a foyer, but it's still unsettling.

38:57

Give me a sense of how people did used to die.

39:01

So often if you had a terminal

39:03

illness by cancer or heart disease,

39:06

there were far fewer treatments in there are today,

39:09

So you're running time, so to speak,

39:11

between when you got ill and when you would die and

39:13

when you would make lucidity before you die would actually

39:15

be longer, so people would have a sense

39:18

they were dying, and they could call their family together.

39:20

They could call the priests for the last rites, or the

39:22

minister to say a blessing or of a rabbi to

39:25

say farewell.

39:26

They could rewrite their will.

39:28

There are all sorts of both cases in mystery

39:30

novels in the nineteenth and early twentieth century

39:32

about rewriting wills. And that's because

39:34

people have this window that we really don't

39:36

have today, because people live

39:39

until their bodies essence shut down.

39:41

I think a related question.

39:44

Is so George

39:46

Church, who's a biologist

39:49

at Guganticist d at Harvard, talked

39:51

about the prospect of bringing

39:53

back not just people who've been deceased, bringing

39:55

back species that have been deceased, and specifically

39:58

human species. I made

40:00

species like Neanderthal man, and

40:02

that raises a whole set of complex related

40:04

questions of its own, of what rights Neanderthals

40:07

would have in the context of human

40:09

society, whether bringing the back would cause them

40:11

existential suffering, whether they would have

40:13

the same rights as Homo sapiens.

40:15

But in the relation to this context, it also

40:18

risk the possibility of bringing back Neanderthals

40:20

who are not Homo sapiens

40:23

and using bare bodies to transplant

40:25

human heads into which might plausibly

40:28

be doable at

40:30

some point in the future, and raise really

40:32

complex ethical questions.

40:51

Let me ask you this you're a psychiatrist, among

40:53

other things, what would you do if you were

40:55

assigned the revivification

40:58

of a Neanderthal man and you

41:00

were the first person in the room when

41:02

he wakes up. Now, obviously you wouldn't share the same language,

41:05

So what would you try to do to

41:08

reduce existential suffering

41:10

on his part?

41:13

I think first I would try to reduce existential suffering

41:15

on my part by standing behind something

41:17

very large, because my

41:20

census Neanderthals waking up

41:22

in this situation might not.

41:23

Be very friendly.

41:25

But beyond that, I think the real answers

41:27

we don't know in the same way we don't

41:29

know how to communicate with dolphins, so they may have

41:31

a very sophisticated language of their own. We

41:34

may have any idea how to communicate

41:36

or appreciate the emotional response of a Neanderthal

41:39

man. It's taken us many, many

41:41

years to understand in a most rudimentary

41:43

way the relationships human beings have with

41:46

other high word er apes like a relige, chimpanzees

41:48

or arangutans. Neanderthals

41:51

will be intellectually far more sophisticated.

41:53

Are going to be a puzzile we first made them. If we first

41:55

made them.

41:56

So what would you actually do if you were assigned

41:59

that.

42:00

Job as a psychiatrist.

42:02

I would probably wait. I would probably

42:04

do nothing until I first see how

42:08

this revived creature responds to me and

42:10

take cues from them in the same way I would do

42:12

seeing any other patient in the emergency room. And

42:14

I I am not comparing any of my patients

42:17

to Neanderthal men, though they may compare me to

42:19

one. But I

42:21

do think it's important first take cues from your

42:23

patients, to take cues from

42:25

other individuals what they expect from

42:27

you. And that's what I think the wisest course of

42:30

action would be.

42:32

Great, God, this is going to be a Hollywood

42:34

screenplay that we should write,

42:36

Okay, any any other thing.

42:39

And I think that covers my end of life

42:41

thinking. I have lots

42:43

of other issues I can always.

42:44

Talk about, but.

42:47

Give me, give me a sense of one.

42:49

Sure. I think one issue that is related but

42:51

distinct.

42:54

Is the situation of conjoined twins

42:57

who wish one twin wishes

42:59

to be separated and the other twin does not wish

43:01

to be separated because of the risk involved in the procedure.

43:04

And you have a situation.

43:05

Where one person's life is at stake

43:07

for the other person, the autonomy and welfare

43:10

of their being is at stake, And there's no

43:12

easy way to resolve that question. And it sort

43:14

of brings to bear all of the different ethical issues

43:16

we have raveled with his society bioethically

43:19

over the last fifty years, and that it's one of

43:21

the only questions in bioethics, by the way, where

43:24

not only do I not have a path to help people move

43:26

forward, I have no visceral sense of what

43:28

the right answer is either. I feel like if I'm not in

43:30

that situation, I can't even think about how to approach

43:32

it.

43:34

Wow, are there other situations

43:36

where one person's

43:38

life would be in danger if something

43:41

happened that would help another person? There must be

43:43

other situations that are analogous.

43:46

Yeah, I mean there's the famous case of Shimp versus

43:48

McFall, where there were two

43:50

cousins and one of them made a bone

43:53

marrow transplant and his cousin was

43:55

the only person in the entire world with

43:57

a bone marrow transplant that could match him that

44:00

he needed to save his life. And he did

44:02

not have a negative relationship with his cousin, but they weren't

44:04

particularly close and he went to his cousin

44:06

and said, please give me the bone marrow transplant,

44:08

and the bone mara trus plant was not high risk,

44:10

but it had some risk in some discomfort. And

44:12

his cousin said, no, I don't owe you that. And

44:15

then he went before the court and said, I'm going to die

44:17

without this bone marrow. It's not that much of an inconvenience

44:20

or risk to my cousin. Please make him do it. And

44:22

the court said no, and

44:24

I believe he died.

44:26

Oh

44:28

do you know anything about what the cousin's reasoning

44:30

was beyond the inconvenience.

44:34

I don't think, and I am not an expert in his case,

44:36

but I don't think the cousin had a great deal of health literacy.

44:38

And the cousin was someone who was a fairly suspicious

44:41

of medicing a baseline. So no matter how

44:43

many times you might tell him he's got a high risk procedure,

44:45

it's not so clear he really believed that.

44:47

Okay, incredible,

44:51

And.

44:51

I will add, by the way, even though that seems

44:54

like a shocking case, every single one of us

44:56

has the ability to save the life of a stranger.

44:59

You can give a a.

45:00

Kidney or part of a liver, and

45:03

some people do altruistically and save someone's

45:05

life, someone who will otherwise die, and

45:08

the vast majority of us, for reasons,

45:10

whether wise or.

45:11

Not wise, choose not to. So in

45:13

some sense we're all mister

45:15

ship.

45:18

Yeah, and we all risk

45:21

being mister McFall too.

45:22

At some point we should not forget right.

45:25

So what do you advise your students on that

45:28

front?

45:30

I mean, I think I advised them in the same way by

45:32

advised students about every ethical issue,

45:35

which is I can't tell you what the right

45:37

answer is. The two things that are important,

45:40

actually, there are three things that are important. The first one is recognized

45:42

and said it is an ethical issue, many of the difficult

45:44

problems that arise in medical ethics, or because no

45:46

one matter how wise or well attention, actually

45:49

recognize this is an ethical challenge. The

45:52

second thing that's really important is

45:54

that when you start with a certain premise, you want

45:56

to logically come to a conclusion based on that premise.

45:58

So at some point between your premise in your conclusion

46:01

a miracle happens here, so to speak, you

46:03

want to.

46:03

Go back to square one.

46:05

And then finally, I say, once you reach

46:08

those two premises, the

46:10

final step is to recognize that very

46:12

well intentioned people with very good values

46:15

come to very different answers about this questions

46:17

from starting with different premises and different

46:20

cultural beliefs and values of their own, and the

46:22

goal is to understand them and respect them even

46:24

if you don't agree with them, because they're

46:26

not fools simply because they disagree with you. And

46:28

I think our society as a whole would be a much better

46:30

place we were able to agree

46:32

to disagree with mutual respect, and we actually would

46:34

be able to find a lot more common ground

46:37

at the corners of a lot of issues where there might be a lot

46:39

of overlap.

46:44

So that was my interview with Jacob Appel,

46:46

one of a very small group of people

46:49

who can equally address both the medical

46:51

and legal and ethical aspects

46:54

of death and the complexities

46:56

at the interface. What I

46:58

hope you've gathered from today's episode

47:00

is that the issue of declaring death is

47:03

not straightforward, and often

47:05

we find the most complex cases

47:07

at the intersection of medical and legal

47:10

systems, and zooming

47:12

out to the beginning, I just want to remind us

47:14

that although we think of death as

47:16

binary, it's often much

47:18

more complex and we are always

47:20

going to be confronted with these problems. As

47:23

technology improves, we're

47:25

going to be able to rescue a life from

47:27

different states that would have been previously

47:30

impossible to reverse or even

47:32

imagine reversing. And

47:34

so as biology marches

47:36

along each year into the future, the

47:38

answer to the question of when

47:41

you are dead is one that will

47:43

change along in lockstep,

47:46

and in two hundred years we

47:48

might find our current answers unpalatable

47:51

and inconceivable. But

47:54

in any case, in each generation, with

47:56

each landscape of new technology,

47:59

we have to con continually revisit

48:01

this question, where do we draw the

48:04

line between life

48:06

and death? Go

48:12

to Eagleman dot com slash podcast

48:14

for more information and to find further

48:16

reading. Send me an

48:18

email at podcasts at eagleman

48:20

dot com with questions or discussions, and

48:22

I'll be making an episode soon in which I address

48:25

those. Until

48:28

next time, I'm David Eagleman, and

48:30

this is Inner Cosmos.

Unlock more with Podchaser Pro

  • Audience Insights
  • Contact Information
  • Demographics
  • Charts
  • Sponsor History
  • and More!
Pro Features