Podchaser Logo
Home
The History of Freedom w/Lea Ypi: Kant, Enlightenment and Peace

The History of Freedom w/Lea Ypi: Kant, Enlightenment and Peace

Released Sunday, 7th April 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
The History of Freedom w/Lea Ypi: Kant, Enlightenment and Peace

The History of Freedom w/Lea Ypi: Kant, Enlightenment and Peace

The History of Freedom w/Lea Ypi: Kant, Enlightenment and Peace

The History of Freedom w/Lea Ypi: Kant, Enlightenment and Peace

Sunday, 7th April 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Rate Episode

Episode Transcript

Transcripts are displayed as originally observed. Some content, including advertisements may have changed.

Use Ctrl + F to search

0:00

Hey, I'm Ryan Reynolds. Recently, I asked

0:02

Mint Mobile's legal team if big wireless

0:04

companies are allowed to raise prices due

0:06

to inflation. They said yes. And then

0:09

when I asked if raising prices technically

0:11

violates those onerous two-year contracts, they said,

0:13

what the f*** are you talking about,

0:15

you insane Hollywood a*****e? So to

0:17

recap, we're cutting the price of Mint Unlimited from $30 a

0:19

month to just $15 a month. Give

0:22

it a try at mintmobile.com/switch. $45

0:25

up front for three months plus taxes and fees. Promote for new

0:27

customers for limited time. Unlimited more than 40 gigabytes per month. Mint

0:29

Unlimited slows. Hello,

0:43

my name is David Runsterman, and this

0:45

is Past, Present, Future. Today's

0:47

episode in our series about the history of freedom

0:50

with the philosopher and writer, and what we're going

0:52

to talk about today in a little

0:54

bit, is about another philosopher, Immanuel

0:56

Kant, and his ideas,

0:58

his ideals for enlightened freedom

1:01

and perpetual peace. We

1:03

talk about just how realistic or

1:05

unrealistic that ideal is and

1:08

about the limits of freedom of thought and

1:11

freedom of expression. Present

1:15

Future is brought to you in partnership with the

1:17

London Review of Books, and the LRB has got

1:19

a brand new podcast out

1:21

now. It's about the sinking of the

1:23

General Belgrano, the bloodiest, the

1:25

most controversial action of the Falklands War,

1:27

and the diary that reveals

1:30

what really happened. It's

1:32

hosted by Andrew O'Hagan, and you can get it now.

1:35

Just go to lrb.me slash

1:37

Belgrano, or wherever you

1:40

get your podcasts. Thank

1:47

you. philosopher,

2:00

some of it is pretty difficult, I can testify

2:02

to that. But he also says

2:04

things that are really easy to grasp and quite

2:06

intuitive. And I want to start with one of

2:09

those. So there's a puzzle that Kant

2:11

writes about that I think everyone

2:13

will recognize, which is

2:15

when you think about human freedom, there

2:18

are two aspects of it that are hard

2:20

to reconcile. So one is clearly to be

2:23

a free human being is

2:25

to be free to do whatever you like. At

2:27

some level, to be human

2:29

is to have the ability, unlike animals

2:31

and other creatures, to

2:33

make your own mind up. And if

2:35

you are unconstrained, that

2:38

could result in almost anything. The

2:40

human brain is capable of coming to

2:42

almost any decision or any choice. And

2:45

yet when you look at how human beings behave

2:47

en masse, they tend

2:49

to conform to certain patterns.

2:52

They weirdly exercise their freedom

2:55

in ways that make it feel like they've

2:58

all been told to do the same thing.

3:00

So the example that I think of here,

3:02

and I always think this every election time

3:04

when I watch the election coverage on

3:06

the BBC or wherever it is, so people

3:08

have voted in Britain and however many it

3:11

is, tens of millions of people vote. There

3:13

have been opinion polls, but then on

3:15

the night you discover what people actually

3:17

have decided. And there's an

3:19

exit poll, they asked a small number

3:22

of people in various places. And this

3:24

exit poll actually tells you how everybody

3:26

voted. And it's incredibly

3:28

accurate. And I find myself thinking,

3:30

so just because these people in this part of the country

3:32

have decided to do this, it's not like they told the

3:35

people in the other part of the country to do the

3:37

same thing, but they are going to do the same thing.

3:40

There is going to be a pattern to

3:42

this free exercise, unconstrained exercise of human choice,

3:44

because despite the fact that just because people

3:46

in Yeoville have voted this way, people 50

3:49

miles down the road could have done something

3:51

completely different, but they don't. They

3:53

do the same thing. They maybe don't do

3:55

what they said in the opinion polls they would do.

3:57

They've exercised their freedom to make their own mind up

4:00

on the... a day. But they've done the thing that

4:02

the people 50 miles down the road did without having

4:04

to be told. But it's almost as though what you

4:07

do when you do the exit poll is you've

4:09

asked the people who told all the other people

4:11

how to vote and it works. And that is

4:13

what Kant is writing about. He's writing about this

4:16

weird tension in human behavior between the obvious discretion

4:18

that we have not to do what other people

4:20

do and the fact that we do do what

4:22

other people do. And he has an answer for

4:25

this. How come those two things are both true?

4:27

Yeah. And I think it's something to do with

4:29

the nature of what we are as human beings.

4:32

I think Kant thinks that reason

4:34

is both disrupting a pattern and conforming

4:36

to a pattern. Both of these are

4:39

our capacities. And indeed, they're

4:41

both our vulnerability. The kind of Achilles

4:43

heel is that we have this. But

4:45

they're also our strength. And in a

4:47

way, the entire Kantian project, the entire

4:49

critical project is to be able to

4:52

articulate an account of reason and

4:54

how reason operates within humans that

4:56

helps them think about their decisions and

4:59

be aware of both the dangers

5:01

and the promises of our use

5:03

of our capacities. What

5:05

I really like is in many ways

5:07

the contemporary. There's a number of things

5:10

that he says about humans, about reason,

5:12

about our societies that are really resonance

5:14

for today. And one of them is

5:16

this tendency of reason to

5:19

struggle with two things. One is dogmatism

5:21

and one is skepticism. And the entire

5:23

Kantian project and the project of reason

5:25

is to help and to help us

5:27

think through this. How can we avoid

5:29

both dogmatism, that is to say conforming

5:31

and accepting authority and endorsing what other

5:33

people tell us, falling, complying into a

5:35

pattern without questioning it? And on the

5:37

other hand, skepticism, which is the opposite,

5:39

to question everything and to then not

5:41

have the resolve to do certain things

5:44

because you're too questioning. And there's a

5:46

kind of paralysis of action that leads.

5:49

He thinks that the modern predicament is

5:51

always torn between those two. And that is

5:53

only if you think about reason. His

5:56

entire project is one that tries to

5:58

help humans reason in such a way

6:00

that they can. can steer a middle

6:02

path between these two things, dogmatism and

6:04

scepticism. And I think that's really resonance

6:06

today as well. You think about the

6:08

world right now. This is really what

6:10

we find ourselves, is scepticism, despair, lack

6:12

of alternative on the one hand, and

6:14

on the other hand, authority, tradition, compliance,

6:16

conformity, following a pattern. Part of the

6:18

reason we follow a pattern though is

6:20

that we are part of nature and

6:22

nature has patterns. And so we

6:24

are part of that. And we are the

6:26

creatures who can understand that. So

6:29

presumably animals can't. Animals follow these

6:31

patterns, but they don't know that's what

6:33

they're doing. But if you know that you're

6:35

following a pattern, that's also the thing

6:38

that allows you to exercise your discretion

6:40

not to follow a pattern. But we

6:42

struggle with that all the time too.

6:45

We simultaneously probably overstate the extent to

6:47

which it's us making up our own

6:49

minds. I'm voting this

6:51

way because I'm a free person and

6:54

I get to exercise my choice. I know, look, I

6:56

voted like all the people in Yeoville or wherever it

6:58

is, even though I've never met them. And

7:01

I think I'm a different person. I'm a

7:03

free independent person, but I am actually conforming

7:06

to a pattern. And so isn't part of

7:08

the project also that in each case, so

7:10

we can overstate the extent to which we

7:12

are free in that

7:14

first sense that we are just an individual, an

7:16

autonomous individual making up our own mind, because we're

7:18

not, we're part of a whole set of natural

7:21

patterns in the natural order of the world. And at

7:23

the same time, we can overstate the extent to which

7:25

we're part of the natural order of the world, because

7:28

we're human. And to be human is

7:30

different from just being part of

7:33

all of the rest of nature. I think what

7:35

is really interesting about the way in which this

7:38

kind of Kantian project developed is it starts with

7:40

this idea that we are part of the pattern.

7:42

But on the other hand, we are also the

7:44

source of the patterns that we identify in nature,

7:46

because the concept of a scientific law wouldn't be

7:49

there without a mind, without a reason

7:51

that tries to think about, okay, how

7:53

do we structure these phenomena

7:55

that we find in nature? And in a way,

7:58

the whole Kantian project is to try and bring

8:00

the scientific revolutions of the 17th

8:02

century Copernicus into philosophy, into the

8:04

world of social science, into the

8:06

world of human relations by

8:09

saying, yes, there are all these things that

8:11

we find there are these phenomena in nature,

8:13

but without a mind that grasp these phenomena,

8:15

without us being able to analyze and understand

8:18

them and distinguish them and say this is

8:20

a generalization, this is contingent, this is necessary.

8:22

All these decisions that we make are all

8:24

part of our reason and it's because we

8:26

have this capacity for reason and this ability

8:29

to think about the law that we then

8:32

try and find what is the law in

8:34

all the structures that we are part of,

8:36

science, nature, observation of the

8:38

world, but also our social relations and

8:41

that's not a coincidence. I think that

8:43

the whole Kantian project is about the

8:45

moral law. What is the law that

8:48

structures human relations, structures, human conduct? Is

8:50

there something necessary and universal there

8:52

or is it just contingent, generalization,

8:54

habit, convention and obviously he challenges

8:57

all that, but I think there is a

8:59

sense in which it starts from this recognition

9:01

of patterns and our input into patterns.

9:03

And those patterns exist across time as

9:05

well as across space. So in

9:08

my example, people in one part of the country turn out

9:10

to be doing what people in another part of the country

9:12

are doing on the same day, but also

9:15

Kant believes that people a long time ago

9:17

were doing things that it looked

9:19

like they were doing for their own reasons and

9:22

those reasons are pretty inaccessible to us and

9:25

on his version of it, some of them are pretty primitive

9:28

and yet they are leading to something else that

9:30

they can't have known about. They can't

9:32

have been thinking, we're doing this because one day

9:34

it will result in the French Revolution or whatever

9:37

it is and yet we can discern some

9:39

of those patterns and it's teleological. That's his

9:41

word for it. There's a direction of travel

9:44

to human affairs within which human beings

9:46

are both free to completely reject the

9:49

teleology and to do things that make

9:51

no sense in terms of an idea

9:53

of progress or whatever it is. And

9:55

yet in the long run, what you

9:58

get is a form of moral progress. It's

10:01

very controversial what Kant meant actually by teleology

10:03

and how you think about the teleology. I

10:05

personally think that the teleology is not something

10:08

that you find. It's something

10:10

that you reconstruct thinking about what is

10:12

the type of human behavior in history

10:15

and what is it driven by. And Kant thinks

10:17

that it is driven by reason. It's driven

10:19

by the imperatives of reason. And to

10:21

the extent that you try and identify those

10:23

reasons and ask yourself, are they moral reasons

10:25

or are they prudential reasons? You can tell

10:28

a story that applies more generally to humans

10:30

across space and time. And so you can

10:32

tell a story about how they interact and

10:34

you can then have a narrative of progress

10:36

or regress in history. And I

10:38

think maybe this is what distinguishes Kant from

10:40

some other later versions of teleology.

10:43

I don't think there is anything deterministic in

10:45

Kantian teleology. It's really all about

10:47

how humans as driven by

10:50

reasons act in history and

10:52

in their societies and the extent to

10:54

which we can reconstruct those reasons as

10:56

moral reasons and say insofar as we

10:58

see anything like something that

11:01

resembles moral motives, moral imperatives

11:03

that advances our capacity for morality, we can

11:06

say that there is progress. If we can't

11:08

find that, then we can't say that

11:10

there is progress. It's just regressive and

11:12

it's just a kind of random arbitrary

11:14

listing of events and characters and history

11:16

is just a sum, a collection of

11:18

stuff that happens, but there's no philosophical

11:20

history. Phenosophical history depends

11:22

on our ability to maintain firm

11:25

that commitment to morality as we

11:28

observe historical events unfold. And

11:30

Kant thinks that what makes us human is that

11:32

we are reasoning creatures. In a way that's

11:35

the difference between a human and an animal

11:37

is that we have reason and animals don't

11:39

have reason. And our reason is

11:41

both, as I say, a source of error

11:43

because reason gets you into all kinds of

11:45

mistakes and prejudice and problems and tragedies in

11:47

a way of reason. But it's also if

11:49

you are able to then reflect critically with

11:51

all of Kant's books that with a

11:53

critique of pure reason, critique of practical

11:55

reason, critique of judgment, if

11:57

you think about the critique of reason, then

12:00

you can help reason unfold in

12:02

a way that is more aligned

12:04

to moral commitments. One

12:06

of the patterns that, as I understand it,

12:08

and you can correct me if I'm wrong, can't discern

12:11

in history, is that using

12:14

our reason, we can all understand that it would

12:16

be better for us if we

12:18

got along better. You are

12:20

freer apart from anything else if you

12:22

live in a society or in a

12:24

world which doesn't have conflict, doesn't have

12:26

war. War is the great enemy of

12:28

freedom. So best to use our reason

12:30

to avoid war. And at the same

12:32

time, we are drawn to conflict. And

12:35

actually, many of the ways in which we exercise

12:37

our reason draw us into conflict with each other,

12:39

because not just that we don't agree about things,

12:42

but we fundamentally loathe some of the things that

12:44

other human beings tell us are

12:46

the truth. And his term for this is

12:49

on social socialability. That is, we're pulled

12:51

in these two different directions. We're pulled

12:53

towards conflict, and this connects

12:55

us to Machiavelli again. But we're

12:58

also pulled by our reason towards an

13:00

understanding that concord or agreement would be

13:02

better for us and better for the

13:04

exercise of our freedom. And this is what

13:06

it means to be human. I mean, this

13:08

is what it means to be part of nature,

13:10

but also in nature, they're not doing the reasoning

13:12

bit. As reasoning creatures, we

13:14

are pulled in these two different directions.

13:16

And yet out of that, this

13:19

is how reason ultimately leads to freedom.

13:22

Because out of our knowledge,

13:24

our understanding that our desire

13:26

for peace has to coexist with

13:28

our impulse to exercise our freedom

13:30

to produce conflict, we create the

13:32

institutions, the rules by which we

13:35

can be constrained. So it's this

13:37

weird combination of what you might

13:39

think of as an

13:41

ideal notion of a collective good

13:44

and peace, and something

13:46

that's more like those philosophers of conflict,

13:48

Machiavellian Hobbes, who think that we need

13:50

to be tamed, but to

13:52

be a reasoning creature is to understand both

13:54

those things. Yeah, and I

13:56

think what's really interesting, and that makes Kant

13:59

in some ways... reflecting on this issue

14:01

in a way that's similar to how Christian

14:03

authors thought about it is the fact that

14:05

both of these tendencies for conflict and for

14:07

harmony are within reason and they're

14:09

part of the use of reason. Kant

14:12

at some point in a book called Religion

14:14

Within the Limits of Reason talks about the

14:16

conflict, the fight between the evil principle and

14:18

the good principle as principles that are both

14:21

part of what it means to be human

14:23

as incentives that we are both driven by.

14:25

And indeed it looks as though

14:27

we wouldn't be free, we wouldn't have free will

14:29

and this is where the kind of overlap with

14:31

the Christian tradition is there wouldn't be free will

14:33

if there was no possibility of error, if there

14:36

was no evil, if evil was something that happens

14:38

outside the mind or outside reason

14:40

or outside what it means to be

14:42

human. It's exactly the fact that it's

14:44

part of who we are that makes

14:46

it a challenge and problem to resolve

14:48

that requires being more sophisticated in how

14:50

you go about thinking about. And Kant

14:52

goes through different stages in his thinking.

14:54

There is an earlier stage where he

14:56

thinks of nature as something that could

14:58

potentially help as something

15:00

like a providential intervention that

15:03

prompts humans that brings them in

15:05

these conflicts. There is something

15:07

that we can detect in nature a tendency

15:10

to help us resolve these conflicts

15:12

and through war come to an

15:14

agreement to make peace and to cooperate with

15:16

each other. And I think there is a

15:18

later understanding that to some extent goes along

15:21

with Kant's changes in how he thought about

15:23

teleology and how he thought about purposeiveness

15:25

more generally both in nature and in

15:27

reason whereby he becomes much more institutionally

15:29

explicit and where it's all about the

15:31

kinds of politics that we have rather

15:33

than the help that nature gives us

15:36

in terms of resolving these conflicts

15:38

and these contradictions. There's earlier point where

15:40

he thinks well nature is going to make us come

15:43

to forms of understanding and to

15:45

political institutions that will enable us

15:47

to resolve our problems and there

15:49

is a later stage where he thinks well

15:51

and usually this coincides with the

15:53

French Revolution and the impact that the French Revolution

15:56

had on Kant's thinking where he thinks well actually

15:58

it's when humans become their own. agents

16:00

they take their faith in their own

16:02

hands politically, that they then have a

16:04

chance of going in a more productive

16:07

cooperative direction. So which of those two

16:09

is the more pessimistic? Because, so

16:12

in response to the French Revolution,

16:14

can't see that human beings can

16:17

really rest control of this very

16:19

long and complicated story. At

16:22

the same time, there are lots of aspects of

16:24

the French Revolution that would give one pause as

16:26

to the ability of human beings to

16:28

somehow naturally come to an understanding of

16:30

what should happen next. And

16:33

this thing can spiral out of control

16:35

very, very quickly. And the

16:37

danger of doing it without lots of

16:39

institutional hemming in is it turns into

16:41

a catastrophe. Yeah, and that's what a lot

16:43

of contemporaries of Kant, including someone like Burke,

16:45

for example, thought. And that was the reason

16:48

for why they were against the French Revolution,

16:50

because they exactly when people become too confident

16:52

of themselves and of their own capacities

16:54

to resolve problems that they can become

16:56

tyrannical and they're these rigorous

16:58

forms of domination. I think Kant

17:00

thought of the French Revolution as one of

17:03

the most progressive events in the history of humanity.

17:06

And in particular, when he writes about this, it's not

17:08

just about the French Revolution as such and

17:10

the revolution as brought

17:13

about by the protagonists of revolution. It's a

17:15

lot about the effects that the

17:17

French Revolution had on those who are watching it, even

17:20

from Prussia or from outside France, basically. Not

17:22

in the theater of war, not in the

17:24

theater of revolution. He writes of

17:26

this as one of the most progressive

17:28

events in the history of humanity, because

17:30

he thinks that there is something tells

17:33

us about our ability to observe

17:36

events with impartiality. So

17:38

he says the spectators to the French

17:40

Revolution see people overthrowing authority, the authority

17:42

of the church or of the monarchy,

17:44

these institutions that they've been for centuries living

17:46

under. And there is a sort of expressive

17:49

element to just being able to get rid

17:51

of that. And he

17:53

thinks that the reaction

17:55

that the French Revolution triggers of

17:57

enthusiasm around those who are observing

18:00

this phenomenon and wanting it to

18:02

go well for the revolutionaries tells

18:04

us something about our moral capacities,

18:06

our moral dispositions and about the

18:09

fact that there is some hope

18:11

that things will go well because we

18:14

have this impartial tendency to just be

18:16

sympathetic to this moral happening in a

18:18

way. So it's really interesting. It's not

18:20

about what they do, what the French

18:22

revolutionaries do, which in many ways also

18:26

rose, as you say, to disaster and

18:28

has produced all these tragedies. It's more

18:30

about how those who were outside the

18:32

theater of war, the theater of revolution,

18:35

think about those events and the ability

18:37

to participate in them and to be

18:39

interested in them even though their interests

18:41

are not at stake. The way in

18:43

which politics helps us reflect about the

18:45

moral structure of our moral dispositions that

18:47

is for count what is singling

18:49

out this event as progressive or as he says,

18:51

he calls it a sign of human progress in

18:54

history. You watch the French Revolution,

18:56

you watch it unfold from the outside, the

18:58

initial event, many people thought this was

19:00

the great dawn of human freedom and

19:02

then you see the terror,

19:04

that's one thing and you might think that's a contingency

19:06

and it doesn't have to go that way. But

19:09

then you see something more familiar and

19:11

certainly more familiar to anyone who'd studied

19:14

human history, which was the great explosion

19:16

of freedom is replaced

19:18

not just by repression, but

19:21

by the re-establishment of familiar

19:23

patterns of political domination from

19:25

revolution to terror, but from

19:27

terror to military rule, for

19:29

military rule, to the rise

19:31

of Napoleon, to empire,

19:33

to European war and to the

19:35

re-establishment then of what

19:37

the other European powers felt was a

19:40

more comfortable order, which then guaranteed a

19:42

form of peace, but the dreams of

19:44

the revolution by that point to a

19:46

certain extent anyway have died. So

19:49

where then if you're looking at it from

19:51

the outside, do you take your inspiration for

19:53

freedom? Is it that what this at least

19:55

shows is that the pattern can be broken

19:57

even though in other ways the pattern reasserts

19:59

itself? itself. It reasserts itself always

20:01

in a new way. Nothing, you don't

20:03

erase the French Revolution from history, even

20:06

when you reassert the familiar pattern of

20:08

European power structures. Is

20:10

that it or is it the thought that next time it

20:13

will be better? Or is it the thought that we could

20:15

do it differently or that we've learned the lesson? Is it

20:17

a lesson learning thing? The latter

20:19

for me, but to go back and I'll start with Kant and then

20:21

I'll get to how I think about it. Kant

20:23

didn't live to see the decline of the

20:25

revolution of the Republic on the rise of Napoleon

20:27

or any of that. He didn't see that. But

20:30

he did live to see the terror and

20:32

it's really interesting that unlike many of his

20:34

contemporaries, he was not bothered by terror. He

20:36

was actually saying that some of the accounts

20:38

of his contemporaries were writing about all the

20:40

things that the French revolutionaries do and the

20:42

terror of Jacobins and so on is nothing

20:44

compared to the pressure and the tragedies

20:46

that the exercise of authority before the

20:48

French revolutionaries came, if you think about

20:50

it in a cumulative way produced.

20:53

And that's really interesting because Kant was not a consequentialist. He

20:55

was not into kind of weighing benefits and burdens.

20:58

So it's very interesting that his contemporaries record him

21:00

as saying this, that it's interesting that

21:02

he has this position where he thinks

21:04

there's this rupture and this fundamental moment

21:07

where something happens that can't quite be

21:09

accounted by moral standards, but that maybe

21:11

needs to be looked at with hindsight

21:13

of historical development and with a philosophical

21:15

reconstruction of history. Does that give

21:17

you pause? It gives me pause. It

21:21

makes me anxious about Kant. None

21:24

of the philosophers that we are studying were usually

21:26

particularly nice person. Why should it be this

21:28

pause? I'm sort of interested in the thoughts

21:30

and thinking about what can I

21:32

take from that, but the fact that they

21:35

make particular pronouncements on any given topic of

21:37

the day, they usually weren't always what we

21:39

would think or hope that they would be.

21:41

I associate a sense that terror

21:44

comes out in the wash of human history

21:47

with many of the

21:49

worst political outcomes of the politics that

21:52

comes later and the

21:54

great terrors of the 20th century, which

21:56

to be honest, don't really

21:58

come out in the wash of human

22:00

history. human history, the millions, the many

22:02

millions dead in the 20th

22:05

century, in the full range of those terrors.

22:07

Maybe it makes me a small L

22:09

liberal or small C conservative. I

22:13

find it uncomfortable even

22:16

starting on the road of

22:19

allowing that if

22:21

you take a long enough view, these

22:24

horrors pale because

22:27

this is your time and this is

22:29

your world and in your time in

22:31

your world they don't pale. Which

22:33

is why I don't think he was

22:35

grounding his defense of the French Revolution

22:37

on these justifications. This is not his

22:40

argument. This is something that I was saying anecdotally.

22:42

He was saying to his friends who were going

22:44

around and saying the Jacobins and so on and

22:46

he said, well, the institutions are right, the republic

22:48

is right and what the church did, what the

22:50

monarchy did, what the massacres of the religious wars,

22:53

you have to factor all of that in and if

22:56

you think about all of those things then maybe we need

22:58

to keep a perspective in check on what

23:00

we think about how we assess the Jacobins. And

23:03

he certainly then wasn't familiar with what happened after

23:05

what kind of president the Jacobin said or anything

23:07

like that. He just thought this is a pattern

23:09

of violence that is part of human history has

23:11

always been then was not invented by the Jacobins.

23:14

For me the interesting question is and this is where

23:16

I want to go back to what you said at

23:18

the end, what gives me hope that things will be

23:21

different? Well I think if you have this philosophical

23:23

perspective on history where you think there is

23:25

a tendency to learn from one's mistakes and

23:27

we can create institutions that channel

23:30

that tendency and we can self-correct

23:32

and we do create rights and

23:34

forms of protection for individuals from

23:37

the abuses of authority and

23:39

we don't want to lose those which

23:41

is why I don't think we should be

23:43

completely anarchist about institutions. We might want to

23:45

replace them but I don't think the

23:48

replacement is arbitrary. It needs to

23:50

be replaced by something that preserves

23:52

the benefits of the predecessor institutions

23:54

and remedies on their pitfalls and there is a

23:56

kind of learning curve there that I think

23:59

should be a good thing. be part of how

24:01

we think about politics and its relationship to morality.

24:03

It's a self-correcting mechanism.

24:06

But to be able to have that, you

24:09

do have to have a philosophical understanding of

24:11

history. You do have to be able to

24:13

create connections between our time and that time

24:15

and the previous time. And so

24:17

there needs to be some sense in which there is a

24:19

bigger story that we can tell about how things

24:22

happen and what humans do and what

24:24

they don't do. If we say our

24:26

time now is completely incomparable with

24:28

what happened 200 years ago or if we say

24:32

so there is a kind of temporal

24:34

detachment theory where you say, you know, what

24:36

happens now is completely – it's like different languages. The

24:38

past is a different language and we can't understand it.

24:41

Or likewise, if you say what

24:43

happens in our culture is completely

24:46

unintelligible to somewhere else in the

24:48

world and there is no possibility of communicating, then

24:50

it's not possible to have those forms of learning

24:52

and it's not possible to have this means

24:54

of contact. And that's why I think

24:56

it's really important and unfortunately we've lost

24:58

it, but it's really important to recover

25:01

this philosophical perspective on history which enables

25:03

us to put together claims across time

25:05

and across space with

25:07

the help of something like what can't be

25:10

called reason which is the constant there and

25:12

which is the universal in a way that

25:14

gives you the possibility of mediating and translating

25:16

between these different contextual arguments.

25:19

But in order to learn from the passage of time,

25:21

you also have to have time. So Kant's very clear

25:23

that this is a really messy

25:25

story. The human story is messy. It

25:27

has twists and turns along the

25:30

way. People choose evil. They don't. There's

25:32

nothing that guarantees they're going to choose

25:34

good. It's sometimes catastrophic. But

25:37

it tends to write itself and each

25:39

time it writes itself, there are more

25:42

philosophical resources to draw on in the

25:44

history of philosophy. This

25:46

is the end of the 18th century,

25:48

the dawn of the 19th century, and

25:51

time moves at a particular rhythm. Dramatic

25:53

events happen at the same time. You can

25:55

recognize your world in the world of a hundred years ago

25:58

and you can imagine a world a hundred years ago. years

26:00

to come which is not completely removed

26:02

from your world. So we're now not

26:04

then. We are in the, well

26:07

not even the early 21st century anymore. It's

26:09

getting on, right? Time is getting on. Last

26:12

time with Machiavelli you mentioned climate change. Climate

26:14

change seems to me a good example of

26:17

this which is the temporal frame doesn't feel

26:19

particularly Kantian. The twists and turns

26:21

along the way. On the one hand we're thinking

26:23

about geological time,

26:25

natural time, where the Anthropocene, the

26:27

human story fits into this much,

26:30

much broader story which

26:32

doesn't all depend on human reason. Is

26:34

human reason just another of the forces

26:36

that shape the natural environment and maybe

26:38

catastrophically? And then there's an

26:41

urgency to it which means if we've got

26:43

to wait for the twists and turns and

26:45

the catastrophes to play themselves out, it

26:47

may be too late. And

26:50

if people are now encouraged to think the history

26:52

of philosophy over 200 years, 300

26:54

years, 2000 years, we'll give

26:56

you the resources to think about the institutional

26:59

reforms that allow. We haven't got the time

27:01

for that. And it may not

27:03

be that we are detached from the past because we

27:05

are our own people, but that we

27:07

are facing challenges. Nuclear war it seems to me

27:09

would be the other one where

27:13

political time but also philosophical time

27:15

is now warped in

27:17

ways that take it outside of the ebb

27:20

and flow of Kantian reason. And

27:23

I don't know what I think about that. Probably what I

27:25

think about that is that it's terrifying. Yeah,

27:27

but are you actually convinced of that? My

27:29

comparison is the Lisbon earthquake at some

27:31

point. These philosophers of the Enlightenment, they

27:34

were hit by this event. And if

27:36

you imagine a religious worldview where there

27:38

is a lot of discussion around providence and

27:40

does God love us or not love... The

27:42

reason the Lisbon earthquake made such an impact

27:44

on Enlightenment philosophers at the time was that

27:46

it seemed one of these external shocks that

27:49

sort of forces you to confront all the

27:51

assumptions you make about the benign intervention of

27:53

God or the fact that God loves humans

27:55

and there seems to be all this amount

27:57

of evil that's just produced out of

27:59

nowhere. that you can't quite account for.

28:01

So they face their own catastrophic thinking,

28:04

you know, their own challenges to their own thinking

28:06

and in some ways even more than us

28:08

because they had less tools to predict events

28:10

whereas we have better science and so we

28:13

know more and we that can kind of

28:15

encourage catastrophic thinking but it can also encourage

28:17

a different way of looking at the future

28:19

which is to say well if you do

28:21

certain things then you doesn't need to happen.

28:23

There's nothing inevitable because we are better equipped,

28:25

we have better knowledge, we have better tools,

28:28

we have better understanding of our environment and

28:30

so we are actually paradoxically more in control

28:32

of nature when we know more about it

28:34

than a period where people didn't

28:36

have the same tools and so we're much more at

28:38

the mercy of the elements of external forces. So it's

28:41

kind of paradoxical for me that we have

28:43

this weird twist, right? When we're at the

28:45

moment we actually have more science, more capacity,

28:47

more prediction, better tools. We face

28:49

this catastrophic thinking that's almost

28:52

worse than it was for people who didn't

28:54

have any of that. So that's my pessimistic

28:56

take on this which is that the story

28:58

doesn't develop in that tension

29:01

between reason as the ability that

29:03

we have to understand the world better and

29:06

also reason as the thing that might drive us to do

29:09

bad things and we now

29:11

understand the world much better but we also

29:13

have the capacity to do worse things. We

29:15

could destroy the natural environment. I think nuclear

29:17

war is nothing like the Lisbon earthquake and

29:20

I think that sort of intervention in this story,

29:22

the Lisbon earthquake certainly for the

29:24

people in Lisbon was the equivalent. If you're all

29:26

exactly that's what I was going to say. For

29:29

the people who are captured in any conflict,

29:31

in any war, it doesn't really matter how you die.

29:33

If you're going to die, then for the person who

29:35

dies and the person who are next to the person

29:38

who dies, it really doesn't matter whether it's nuclear war or

29:40

a car crash. No but I'm thinking

29:42

about then the possibility of the recovery as

29:44

the story ebbs and flows along its way,

29:47

the recovery from this. I mean the human

29:49

history is full of apocalypses for the people

29:51

who live through them. In fact, that's the

29:53

dominant story I think but out of it

29:55

comes as Kant would say

29:58

the emergence of the institutions of restraint

30:01

and constraint that make these less likely and

30:03

then using reason something more than that the

30:05

ability of people to behave in a more

30:07

moral way all of that I

30:09

can think of 21st century scenarios where

30:11

that's simply it's not

30:13

plausible that it's part of that gradual

30:17

story of moral progress I mean it's a pessimistic

30:19

view but I don't think it's a unrealistic

30:22

view that that might be what happens

30:24

here but also that tension with you

30:26

know let's call it unsociable

30:29

sociability unsociable sociability

30:32

in the age of climate change and

30:34

nuclear war seems to me a different

30:36

kind of proposition because there are ways

30:39

that the human story can go paths

30:41

that could be taken from

30:43

which there isn't an obvious coming back

30:46

to a Kantian

30:48

philosophy of history yeah and there is

30:50

a demoralizing way and a more empowering

30:52

way of looking at it and so in a

30:54

way the Kantian story of progress is also

30:57

story it is a narrative it's a story

30:59

that we tell ourselves about how we can

31:01

think about history and it's premised on a

31:03

certain understanding of which of the multis that

31:05

shape reason will prevail the good one or

31:07

a bad one so it will go well

31:10

if people act morally it will go badly

31:12

if it if people don't act morally

31:14

I think the problem is that we're in the

31:16

times in which we live we have just actually

31:18

lost faith in the human so we have lost

31:21

faith in our collective capacity and that's also story

31:23

that we've told ourselves and that has taken hold

31:25

of our minds and it exercises

31:27

this epistemological power it we are in its

31:30

hold in the sense that we are unable

31:32

and of course unlike people in the past

31:34

who had religion as well that could sustain

31:36

them we've also lost that so we're in

31:38

a way in a world where a

31:40

lot of the sources traditional sources we

31:43

trust science but only insofar as

31:45

it goes along with this catastrophic

31:47

predictive thinking we don't really

31:49

trust religion we have really not much

31:51

faith in community and in because

31:54

we're in this ultra individualistic societies where

31:56

people are encouraged to fend for themselves

31:58

and help themselves and don't really think

32:00

about social contact. So of course,

32:02

it's hard because the narratives that surround

32:04

us are all narratives of loss of

32:06

faith in the human. And

32:09

in a way what Kant is saying

32:11

in the famous essay in the Enlightenment

32:13

where he says, enlightenment is the process

32:15

of emerging from your own self-incurred immaturity.

32:18

I think we're exactly in that type

32:20

of self-incurred immaturity prediction because you

32:23

could tell the story very differently, it

32:25

could go very differently but of course

32:27

it will only go very differently if

32:29

people act and mobilize and get together

32:31

and try and come up with resources

32:33

that encourage a different narrative to take

32:35

hold. If we just all of us

32:37

sit there and watch the apocalypse and think,

32:39

oh well, nothing can be done anymore, well

32:42

yeah, it will happen and nothing in Kant

32:44

that will stop that from happening and indeed

32:46

there's nothing Kant says that will stop that

32:48

because he's not a fool

32:50

and he doesn't say, well, it

32:52

goes well. The assumption that it

32:54

goes well is premised on us

32:56

acting morally and acting morally also

32:59

means creating the kinds of political

33:01

institutions that channel these moral incentives.

33:03

And when that's not the case, then it doesn't go well.

33:06

It's terrible. Nothing in nature that can help

33:08

you. There's a wonderful paragraph in

33:10

the Critique of Judgment where he says, nature

33:12

doesn't take the human being for their special

33:14

darling. It doesn't spare them pestilence or

33:16

hunger or any of the things that

33:18

it spares other animals to nature for

33:20

a way in which if you just

33:22

take natural perspective, we are just animals

33:24

like any other animal and yeah, of

33:26

course we'll die, we'll fight, we'll be

33:28

extinct like other species of animals get

33:30

extinct. What makes us a little

33:32

bit different is that we have the capacity to

33:35

prevent that from happening if we act in a

33:37

certain way. But it does require us to act

33:39

in a certain way and to think that it's

33:41

possible to act in that way. If we lose

33:43

the faith in the human in that sense, then

33:46

we really, there is no chance. experts

34:00

to ensure quality and authenticity. Use

34:02

ReBag to buy and sell signs from

34:04

the world's top brands including Louis Vuitton,

34:07

Chanel and Cartier. Head to rebag.com to

34:09

get 10% off your

34:11

first purchase with code REBAG10.

34:13

Shop today at rebag.com. That's

34:15

r-e-b-a-g.com and use promo code

34:18

REBAG10 for 10% off your

34:20

first purchase. Hold

34:24

up! What was that? Boring! No

34:26

flavor! That was as bad as

34:28

those leftovers you ate all week.

34:30

Kiki Parma here and it's time

34:33

to say hello to something fresh

34:35

and guilt-free. HelloFresh. Jazz up dinner

34:37

with pecan-crusted chicken or garlic butter

34:39

shrimps can be. Now that's music

34:42

to my mouth. HelloFresh. Let's get

34:44

this dinner party started. Discover all

34:46

the delicious possibilities at hellofresh.com. This

34:53

is a story about freedom and it's also a story

34:56

about peace. If we do that

34:58

we can find a way towards peace in

35:01

a world in which in the political

35:04

versions of this of what it means to

35:06

be human the way it tends to go

35:08

wrong is war and war is one of

35:10

the things that we can choose not through

35:12

natural impulse but because we choose the evil

35:14

right that's one of the things that war

35:16

is and war is evil and it's a

35:18

human choice it's not just we suddenly become

35:20

animals we fight a war then we become

35:22

philosophers and we do peace we're human in

35:24

both of those functions of what

35:27

we do but for Kant

35:29

the arc is towards peace and one

35:31

of the things that he thought at the

35:33

end of the 18th century we could learn

35:36

is that war is kind of unsustainable in

35:38

the long run and one of the reasons he

35:40

thought it was unsustainable and this

35:42

was a classic enlightenment argument it sounds

35:44

quite unphilosophical was the only way in

35:46

the modern world not in the ancient

35:48

world but in the modern world to

35:50

fund these wars was by taking out

35:52

massive debts you had to borrow to

35:54

fight these wars and he just thought

35:57

this is completely unsustainable And rational

35:59

thinking? Human. Things will notices. It may

36:01

take time now. you may have to fight

36:03

some pretty awful was but then you'll twig.

36:05

It's just not worth it. Even if we

36:07

win if you lose it's definitely fighting the

36:09

war. But even if we when we won

36:11

the war but with burdened with all this

36:13

debt in a way we've lost our freedom

36:15

because weeks we're now. In. Debt

36:17

the people who are criticism So we

36:19

will work out that the only way

36:22

to maintain our freedom is to avoid

36:24

this and that will be a path

36:26

to peace. And he was wrong about

36:28

that. We've had this conversation before on

36:30

this book. Us talking about the enlightenment

36:32

in that. The. Most powerful

36:34

states of the modern world have actually found

36:36

a way to sustain that level of that.

36:38

The United States and Twenty Twenty Fours the

36:40

single most indebted institution in human history on

36:43

a scale that can't Would have thought that

36:45

racing human beings would just. Know.

36:47

Is impossible. But it's not impossible.

36:50

And this is also a

36:52

world in which war. Is

36:54

not as prevalent as as ever Been Cool

36:56

less prevalent in some ways but much more

36:58

prevalent than can't would have hoped to hundred

37:00

years after he wrote. Yelled I don't

37:03

think I'm thought that there was a

37:05

again necessity in the disappearance. Of law or

37:07

and in fact but reason would help her see it.

37:09

But. It was also a political act.

37:11

So the famous essay on perpetual piece.

37:14

It's an essay that's that's with the

37:16

idea of having a clause in a

37:18

peace treaty that says there's i'll be

37:20

no war and not a kind of

37:22

temporary peace but death of perpetual feast

37:24

of these that last forever. So he

37:27

was someone with that. The answer to

37:29

not having war is to come up

37:31

with international institutions. And same as argument

37:33

about the Federation of Republican States that

37:35

creates the forms of supra national corporation

37:38

that enables states to then sono their

37:40

antagonisms. In a direction of creating international

37:42

institutions that help them coordinate themselves. Overcome

37:44

A The standard argument in the Enlightenment was that

37:46

we have the state of nature between individuals and

37:49

there is the states And that's why we have

37:51

a safe because otherwise people are fighting. It's other

37:53

And a lot of Enlightenment critics, including fans took

37:55

this one step further and said, well, now you

37:57

have the state of nature between states That does.

38:00

Have these states that are now fighting it's

38:02

other and being like individuals in the fate

38:04

of nights? So how do we make sure

38:06

that we have a mechanism of cooperation? And

38:09

he thought that the argument for perpetual piece

38:11

was exactly that kind of argument were states

38:13

are asked to. Stop fighting,

38:16

Stop funding War. Stops are

38:18

arming themselves. Basically stopped doing all

38:20

of the things that they're doing right now

38:22

and in fact, The. Motivation for

38:24

that was it's only to great

38:27

international institutions with some power over

38:29

these individual states that you can

38:31

create forms of sustainable corporation that.

38:34

Don't need to trigger constant conflicts and

38:36

this is why it's an argument not

38:38

for peace before perpetual peace with as

38:40

much more demanding in a way but

38:42

I think also more promising. Because without

38:44

perpetual bases always have more here

38:46

and there and conflicts and to

38:48

erupt interestingly and his brother. For

38:50

perpetual these woods was not again

38:52

or something a pump came up

38:54

with it woven. Russo mentioned it

38:56

was in some pierre included Rasa

38:58

included the proposal for Federation of

39:00

European States. But with a very

39:03

large, expensive geography. Heads clauses for

39:05

what to do with the Ottoman Empire. Because

39:07

it with a with a question of you know the

39:09

christians versus the others. And sauce. But it was

39:11

very visionary for the time and in some

39:13

ways something that. Should. Still be an inspiration

39:15

for how we think about institutions nowadays.

39:18

I. Saw him as a problem with the

39:20

enlightenment view but you can take the

39:22

next steps of the first up. For

39:25

on social social policies is from.

39:28

Human. Conflict to the institutions of

39:30

the state and then these states

39:32

are in conflict. Me take them

39:34

expect which is to the institutions

39:36

that the steaks them are constrained

39:38

by. Bills. Are within which they

39:40

can expose the freedom of choice and

39:42

letting the floor with that is that.

39:45

Mistakes on human and. They are

39:47

not human and lots of ways including they

39:49

don't reason like human beings do, they reasoned

39:51

like machines. I've always thought that this is

39:53

the fundamental flaw with the whole view of

39:55

the world and. Part. Of my evidence

39:58

for that is that Trump was wrong about that. So

40:01

on a human level. That. Relationship

40:03

to warn that is unsustainable. It

40:05

doesn't make any sense, but it

40:07

makes perfectly good sense for these

40:09

machines which turn out to be

40:12

among other things debt servicing machines

40:14

that give human beings faith That

40:16

actually perpetual indebtedness is the story

40:18

of the modern human condition and

40:20

out of perpetual indebtedness. The United

40:23

States is the classic example of

40:25

this out of perpetual indebtedness. What

40:27

you get is lots of good

40:29

things. the human beings economic growth

40:31

and the rest. But you don't

40:34

get the end of conflict because that

40:36

a credit to relationships are inherently unstable

40:38

and then debt. Is. The Engine

40:40

of War I think you're right that counts

40:42

didn't see that but other people didn't say

40:44

that. Someone like sister for example who on

40:46

the continent many ways. Actually when he wrote

40:48

one of his books everyone thought it was

40:50

an of anonymously and everyone thought it was

40:52

com than so he was kind of the

40:54

nurturing his inner can't even though we ended

40:56

up in a very different place as professional

40:58

fees and up with a celebration of Us

41:01

State than what he calls the cloth Commercial.

41:03

States But in a way. these arguments about

41:05

that, the unsustainability of that and so on,

41:07

what exactly is led him to argue. That

41:09

we need to do something about not death. But.

41:12

The states still book about globalization more generally

41:14

and his answer was what week? Since we

41:16

can't do anything about globalization that we just

41:18

go back to the cloth commercial state and

41:20

stop interacting and some of the globalized and

41:23

and some Then there's the whole debate the

41:25

follows from there it sister was one. Which.

41:27

Is also quite contemporary. Questions. Temporary Rights

41:29

of these? That was one answer. Another argument

41:31

was then Hagan and Mark. Switches difference way

41:34

of thinking about it which is wealth. Why

41:36

don't you? Instead of putting all the

41:38

emphasis on said think about what, Where's

41:40

that coming from? Enceladus? The structure of our

41:43

economic relations and will maybe we'll talk in

41:45

the theater about this at this discussion around

41:47

the market than the relationship of markets to

41:49

the states. but basically the argument. Was then

41:51

or reform not just of the

41:53

states but also the environments, the

41:55

economic environment, Within which states. Operates

41:57

ends the something that will.

42:00

Then enable states to be

42:02

better at creating peace without

42:04

these. Constraints. On them

42:06

with Sar in some ways external and

42:08

constraints of the market rather than produced

42:10

by the states. You. Could

42:13

say one of the reasons we've

42:15

lost our faith in the human

42:17

is that human reason has turned

42:19

out to be remarkably good at

42:22

building artificial agents, artificial decision makers

42:24

including rational decision makers on a

42:26

mechanistic understanding irrationality that are the

42:28

dominant forces in our world that.

42:31

The. State is not simply an expression

42:33

of human reason for best friend. For

42:36

worse, good or evil, it is it's

42:38

own thing. And that

42:40

our world is dominated by these

42:42

vast and cities which are their

42:44

own thing and they are the

42:46

products of human reason. and they

42:48

are. Motivated. By what

42:51

the human beings who build them want to happen,

42:53

but they also require a kind of life of

42:55

the road and the other way in which we

42:57

may not have much time. Is

42:59

that this process is really

43:01

rapidly accelerating. The human reason

43:03

coupled now with the reasoning

43:05

capacity of so called intelligent

43:07

machines artificially intelligent machines is

43:09

a rapid pace creating new

43:11

kinds of decision making and

43:13

cities which again suggests to

43:15

me that. What? You Need

43:17

in the Canteen story, which is the sort of

43:20

back and forth with the West and wolfed whatever

43:22

the phrase would be of the story of human

43:24

reason. That. Story made.

43:26

I've lost face their stories

43:29

over. Yeah. I don't agree with

43:31

that impact because I think maybe we actually have

43:33

a disagreement in terms of how we think about

43:35

the autonomy of these activists Laden so I think

43:37

may I effect you think of and as much

43:39

more autonomous and I think they are. From human

43:41

reason. I think they track

43:44

human reason. It's just that they tracked and not

43:46

a moral side of human reason. So they

43:48

track that kind of instrumentals reason that

43:50

is for then slowly many ways but

43:52

isn't always kind of thinking about morality

43:54

and moral imperatives and science. but that's

43:57

i don't think there's anything essential about that they don't

43:59

need to be doing that. They can

44:01

be designed in different ways and we do

44:03

have agency and these are still

44:06

connected to us, these institutions that we create,

44:08

these artificial agents. It's still

44:10

fundamentally human reason that is at their basis.

44:12

They channel human reason differently in different historical

44:15

periods and because of the constraints and because

44:17

of the environment in which they operate they

44:19

might be different. But I don't think there's

44:21

anything essential about this loss of control which

44:23

is also partly why I'm I think more

44:25

optimistic and not completely despairing because I think

44:27

well they now reflect

44:29

what the sidegeist is and so

44:31

they reflect the dominant tendencies but

44:33

these are tendencies. There is nothing

44:36

essential about them, there's nothing deterministic

44:38

and because we are free and

44:40

we could be different. And I

44:42

think if we concede that humans

44:44

are free we have to

44:46

also concede that they could be different and

44:48

we also have to concede that there's nothing

44:50

predetermined about the way they operate and what

44:52

they create produces. I want

44:54

to ask you about one last idea of freedom which is

44:57

essentially Kantian which is intellectual freedom. Though

45:00

in the essay about enlightenment it's also

45:02

about what it is to live

45:04

in a world where it is absolutely crucial that

45:07

people are able to voice

45:09

dissenting opinions at

45:11

the same time as it is also important

45:14

that you don't descend into anarchy. So

45:16

to summarize it too crudely essentially

45:18

what Kant is saying is that

45:21

at a certain level you must abide by

45:23

the rules of your state but you also

45:25

must be willing to criticize them. That's

45:29

quite Machiavellian in a way,

45:31

it's also quite Socratic

45:33

or Platonic. You know we've been talking

45:35

about different versions of this, the dilemma

45:37

of what we call democracy

45:40

but other people would call republican forms

45:42

of government which is you both need

45:44

to be a good citizen and a

45:46

dissenting citizen. But Kant's

45:49

version of it is very much an

45:52

intellectual version in the sense that he's imagining

45:54

what he calls a republic of letters and

45:57

he's imagining what we would probably think

45:59

of was something close to the

46:02

academic version of this, that there are

46:04

settings in which dissent is

46:06

not just to be

46:08

encouraged. It's absolutely essential among the people

46:10

who are understood as the thought leaders

46:13

and the ones who are communicating to

46:15

a literate public in a world where

46:17

most people were not literate. And so

46:20

it exists within a particular setting.

46:23

And within that setting, you can

46:26

have radical intellectual freedom because

46:28

it's unlikely to leak out into

46:31

a world in which it would lead to people

46:33

no longer obeying the law.

46:35

And that also feels to me quite, let's

46:38

say 19th century, late 18th, 19th century, and

46:41

through to ideals of university

46:43

and educated life in the 20th century, it

46:45

doesn't feel to me very 21st century in

46:48

the age of the kind of information

46:51

space that we live in now, the

46:53

ways in which it's been radically democratized,

46:55

in which the expression of dissent and

46:57

of different opinions has

47:00

spread way beyond the Republic of letters.

47:03

Or maybe we're all now in the Republic of letters, I don't know.

47:05

But it's not that Kantian version in

47:07

which part of what

47:09

makes it work is that you

47:12

can move between these two spaces

47:14

where it's radical freedom of dissent

47:16

and intellectual dissent within a relatively

47:19

stable political space. I

47:22

don't feel that's our world. So

47:24

yes and no, this very interesting discussion, I

47:27

always have this discussion with my students, discussion

47:29

around the enlightenment and how you think about

47:31

the public sphere and the extent to which

47:33

our public sphere or the digital public spheres

47:35

that we have, the extent to

47:37

which they overlap or differ from

47:39

these enlightenment public spheres. And I think there

47:42

is a sense in which predicament is not

47:44

that different in that what Kant is saying

47:46

is, if you're in a particular social role,

47:48

if you're a doctor or a tax collector or

47:51

an administrator or whatever, you just

47:53

have to perform within

47:55

the constraints of that role because otherwise

47:57

you can't be a conscientious objector in

47:59

every type of function that you perform, right?

48:01

So you have to teach certain things, you have to teach

48:03

certain things. You can't just go around, tell the students what

48:06

your opinions are on everything you teach, even though you might

48:08

have an opinion on everything. And that

48:10

applies to, again, to being a doctor, to

48:12

being an engineer, to whatever, being an administrator,

48:15

being a tax collector. So in that

48:17

sense, I think we are still in a society where

48:20

there is division of labor and where all of us

48:22

are performing certain social roles. But then we also have

48:24

something like the ethics of the citizen, where we can

48:26

step out of our social role and criticize the constraints

48:28

of that role, the way in which those roles function.

48:31

And in that sense, it's quite similar. What I

48:33

think is different, and I think you're completely right

48:35

about that, is that we have a notional expansion

48:38

of a public sphere in that for count

48:40

it was basically just educated bourgeois

48:42

and aristocratic men. And, you know,

48:45

there were no women, there were no sense of

48:47

people without property would be included in the public

48:49

sphere and so on. And so in a

48:51

way, formally, right now we have a much more expansive

48:54

public sphere and the more

48:56

potential for emancipation also because it's much

48:58

more the discourse could take on, could

49:00

be wider. But oddly, there's also something

49:03

else that happens, which is then the

49:05

pressure of conformity. And so in our

49:07

contemporary public sphere, there is,

49:09

yes, possibly lots of

49:11

ideas circulating and so on. But in practice, what you

49:14

have is highly disciplined currents

49:16

of thought and thought bubbles

49:18

where you have everyone agreeing within the

49:21

thought bubble and very little then

49:24

transfer from one bubble to the other

49:26

and very little exchange between those. And

49:28

then it becomes again like the Kantian

49:31

context in which he's saying, well, you

49:33

need to be able to step out

49:35

of now not just the role obligations,

49:37

but also the thought bubbles where then

49:39

the enlightenment argument, I think, becomes still

49:41

really relevant because it is an argument

49:43

for exercising reason in an open

49:45

way. And Kant doesn't say, you know,

49:48

just exercise reason, there are constraints of how you exercise

49:50

reason. It's not just that we reason, but there you have

49:52

to reason in a way that puts you

49:54

in a place of everyone else. You have to

49:56

think consistently there is what Kant calls

49:58

the maxims of enlightenment. I'm thinking and

50:01

not have anything goes And then

50:03

you discipline your conversations and then

50:05

you're able within those constraints a

50:07

reason to have conversations. Across these

50:10

different bubbles. And that's is what

50:12

might encourage the public sphere to

50:14

operate, but just. The existence of the

50:16

public sphere and just the openness is not

50:18

going to be gnostic. Of cerro many different

50:21

ways including and contemporary society is in

50:23

which both is disciplined by commerce, by

50:25

incentives, by advertising by but propaganda or

50:27

by the sea or pressure of conformity

50:29

with the appears to so about time.

50:31

Though Canton Republic of Letters moved as

50:33

a relatively sedate pace, you have the

50:35

time to think you had the time

50:37

to respond. If there was going to

50:40

be progress in this world it would

50:42

ever want to do with take a

50:44

lot of time, progress in philosophy and

50:46

we are moving in a particular direction.

50:48

But it takes time we. Don't have

50:50

that time now and then.

50:53

You. Will you are must boot. Twitter.

50:55

And and he called x is the

50:57

phrase uses of i'm buying the global public

50:59

Square That's what I'm doing And for

51:01

this to work, Dawkins become so conformist and

51:04

it's become so regulated we have to

51:06

open up. We go to let them from

51:08

by. Can you know we have to

51:10

break up. These. Bubbles.

51:12

but. Her, It's frankly

51:14

been a disaster, I think. And it's

51:16

be a disaster because it is just

51:18

the unregulated version of it for the

51:21

reasons he said just create new kinds

51:23

of patterns of domination. Yeah, They do,

51:25

but I don't think the problem is time. The

51:27

problem is education. Birch Case and takes

51:29

time bread. But I think that that we have

51:31

to go back to. The source said what is the

51:33

issue that if you have very educated public with as

51:36

a lot of people tend to assume that's one of

51:38

the questions with digital interactions and digital media as everything

51:40

is like Sosa process once a week and then it's

51:42

not enough time for things are highly educated. The fact

51:45

that it's quick could also be an advantage because then

51:47

we could have an argument. Really quickly and then resulted

51:49

in than most of the next argument that would have a

51:51

lot more knowledge. So. I think there is a

51:53

different way of seeing it, which is the

51:55

reason it's now producing the worst pathologies is

51:58

this quickness? And the press and the urgency. combined

52:00

with fundamental ignorance. But the

52:02

fundamental ignorance, again, is not

52:04

essential. It's driven by the

52:07

way in which education works

52:09

and education institutions are funded

52:11

and who gets to benefit and who doesn't. So then we

52:13

go back to all the discussions around access

52:15

to education, what it takes to

52:17

think intellectually and critically. I

52:20

completely understand what you just

52:22

said and I can picture it as

52:25

an ideal, the quick argument

52:27

that produces the answer more quickly

52:29

and allows us to move on.

52:33

We now live in a world where

52:35

that kind of speed has been franchised

52:37

out to machines. It just has and

52:39

I don't think it's coming back. That

52:41

kind of knowledge, the ability to access

52:43

this space so that you can move

52:45

in time with the pace of the

52:48

information, is so reliant now on machines

52:50

which are themselves controlled by and dominated

52:52

by the forces that you just talked

52:54

about. And I don't

52:56

think, my feeling is that this

52:58

has escaped. The story that we've talked about which

53:01

through the 20th century did make

53:03

a lot of sense, we have escaped it

53:05

and part of the reason that we've escaped it, I

53:08

totally also get what you're saying that

53:10

it's tracking one version of human reason.

53:12

But that version of human reason that

53:14

it is tracking has

53:16

now acquired a life of its own. Fine,

53:19

it has escaped. Is the escape irreversible

53:21

or not? Because if you think it's

53:24

irreversible, okay fine, let's close down the

53:26

podcast, go home, get drunk and wait for

53:28

everyone to die. If you say

53:30

it's reversible, the next question is what

53:32

are you doing to reverse it? And

53:35

that's the question that people need to ask themselves.

53:37

It's no point just going around everyone beating each

53:39

other up and say, oh it's so terrible, it's

53:41

escaped, it's out of control. These machines,

53:44

they are designed by humans and we know they

53:46

have all the biases of humans because you go

53:48

and you ask them certain kinds of questions and

53:50

they regurgitate back all the biases which shows that

53:52

there is a kind of design flaw. They could

53:54

be designed differently, yes or no, yes. If

53:57

they could be designed differently, what are we doing to design

53:59

them? It's very simple. Who are you voting for?

54:01

Who are you campaigning for? What are

54:04

you saying? What kind of arguments are you

54:06

making? We all have individual responsibilities in upholding

54:08

the kind of social structures that make up our

54:10

lives. And it's just we don't get out of them

54:12

by just saying it's so terrible we can't do anything

54:14

because actually we can do something, all of us. Do

54:25

subscribe now to PPF Plus where

54:27

you can get ad-free listening, no

54:30

ads on past or future episodes

54:32

of this podcast. And you

54:34

get two bonus episodes to accompany every series

54:36

that we put out. Coming

54:38

soon to accompany this series, there'll be

54:40

an episode in which Leia and I

54:42

talk about what freedom means in the

54:44

age of thinking machines and

54:46

AI. To get

54:48

PPF Plus, just click on the link that

54:51

comes with the show description or go to

54:53

ppfideas.com. You

54:55

can as always follow us on Twitter

54:58

at PPFideas on Instagram and TikTok. And

55:00

there are videos coming

55:02

up next on the history of freedom in

55:04

episode five. We're going to be

55:06

talking about the idea of the free market. Just

55:09

how free are we when we're

55:11

buying, when we're selling, when

55:14

we're borrowing, when we're spending? Do

55:19

join us for that. This

55:21

has been Past, Present, Future brought to you in

55:23

partnership with the London Review of Books. All

55:54

the way to the Did We Just Hit

55:57

a Million Orders stage? Shopify's there to help

55:59

you grow. Shopify helps you turn

56:01

browsers into buyers with the Internet's

56:03

best converting checkout. 36%

56:06

better on average compared to other

56:08

leading commerce platforms. Because businesses that

56:11

grow, grow with Shopify. Get a

56:13

$1 per month trial

56:15

period at shopify.com. shopify.com.

56:20

One Eight Hundred flowers.com is more than

56:22

your birthday anniversary or if just because

56:24

gift giving destination. We put our hearts

56:26

into everything we do to help you

56:29

celebrate all life. Special occasions with friends

56:31

and family from our farmers than bakers,

56:33

florists. The Makers. Everything from

56:35

1-800-Flowers is made with love, every step

56:38

of the way. Because we know that

56:40

nothing is more important than delivering a

56:42

smile. To learn more, visit 1800flowers.com/ACAST.

56:45

That's 1800flowers.com

56:49

slash ACAST.

Unlock more with Podchaser Pro

  • Audience Insights
  • Contact Information
  • Demographics
  • Charts
  • Sponsor History
  • and More!
Pro Features