Podchaser Logo
Home
Why we should question everything | Michael Della Rocca on radical philosophy

Why we should question everything | Michael Della Rocca on radical philosophy

Released Tuesday, 26th March 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Why we should question everything | Michael Della Rocca on radical philosophy

Why we should question everything | Michael Della Rocca on radical philosophy

Why we should question everything | Michael Della Rocca on radical philosophy

Why we should question everything | Michael Della Rocca on radical philosophy

Tuesday, 26th March 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Rate Episode

Episode Transcript

Transcripts are displayed as originally observed. Some content, including advertisements may have changed.

Use Ctrl + F to search

0:03

What do vernal pools, psychedelics,

0:05

and spacetime have in common?

0:08

They're all featured on Scientific

0:10

American's new podcast, Science Quickly,

0:12

which quenches your curiosity in

0:14

under 10 minutes. Find

0:17

it wherever you get your

0:19

podcasts or head over to

0:21

scientificamerican.com/podcasts. Today

0:29

we've got Why We Should Question Everything, an interview

0:32

with Michael DelaRocca. It took place at our London

0:34

How the Light Gets in Festival in 2023. This

0:37

is the philosophy festival produced twice a year by the team

0:39

here at the IAI. So

0:42

Margarita, what did you think about this interview? I

0:44

thought it was a really good

0:46

interview. Michael DelaRocca has a really

0:48

interesting theory that builds on Spinoza

0:50

and really unpacks how language

0:53

is essentially a rollata, what

0:56

he defines as like an infinite

0:58

set of relations that describes reality.

1:01

It's quite innovative and I would say quite

1:03

radical. So a

1:05

great interview if you're interested

1:07

in Quine or Saussure or

1:10

indeed language. Great. Before

1:13

we hand over to Simon, don't forget to

1:15

subscribe, leave a review on your platform of

1:17

choice, and visit iai.tv

1:19

for hundreds more podcasts, videos, and

1:21

articles from the world's leading thinkers.

1:24

A lot of philosophers today really are

1:27

subservient to common sense and to our intuitions.

1:29

And those are different things perhaps, but for

1:31

our purposes they're pretty much the same that people

1:33

feel that we must respect common

1:36

sense beliefs, we must respect our intuitions,

1:39

and a philosophical system has to try

1:41

to accommodate intuitions as much as possible,

1:43

try to accommodate common sense as much

1:45

as possible. But I think that's kind

1:47

of really a bankrupt

1:49

methodology. I think that in terms of

1:51

how one should do philosophy, if one

1:53

is really being guided only by one's

1:56

intuitions or by common sense, then one

1:58

is not really doing it. doing one's

2:00

job as a philosopher because this is

2:02

the methodology of relying on intuitions or

2:05

common sense is inherently

2:07

conservative, I think. It's

2:09

also too much guided

2:12

by our psychology and

2:14

it's ultimately arbitrary. So I think it's really

2:16

not a great way to do philosophy. You

2:18

know, that may be true that we're guided

2:20

in our psychology, maybe our psychologists are

2:23

going to twist our perception

2:25

of reality. But ultimately, you want

2:28

to get at truth and philosophy wants to

2:30

get at truth. So is there a reason

2:32

to think that you've criticized this view for

2:35

being unduly conservative, but maybe the conservative tracks

2:37

the truth in a way that this sort

2:39

of radical methodology does not? Maybe

2:42

so, right? But I think that this kind of, we

2:45

don't know in advance what's going to track the

2:47

truth and we shouldn't close off, we shouldn't constrain

2:49

ourselves from the very beginning, which is methodology

2:52

of common sense relies upon. And so

2:54

really, I'm going to go against a lot of common

2:56

sense views and do so, I think, because

2:59

I think there's a good reason to do so.

3:01

I think that should be the methodology that philosophy

3:03

should be guided for, to follow the reasons where

3:05

they lead. And even if it goes, even those

3:07

reasons lead to a place that's far from common

3:09

sense. Philosophy is

3:12

nothing, if not has

3:14

potential to be radical. And I think that

3:16

that's a kind of a birthright for philosophy

3:19

that it should at least be open to

3:21

kinds of radical changes in views. I

3:24

think this is largely true of

3:26

contemporary and recent analytical philosophy. It's

3:28

really extremely conservative and it

3:30

really is going to

3:32

be too much guided by common sense and

3:35

never really will get to these kinds of

3:37

radical results, which at least should be a

3:39

possibility that should philosophers should not forswear at

3:41

the beginning. So, tell me more

3:43

about these radical results in the book you call it, this

3:45

sort of radical monism. Can you explain sort of

3:47

the view more in detail? So this kind of

3:49

radical monism is the view that there are no

3:52

distinctions. And that's what I mean by monism. There

3:54

are no distinctions. And

3:56

I get to that view because I think

3:58

that there is no... way

4:00

to explain relations

4:03

of distinction. In general,

4:05

for me, relations are not explicable.

4:09

And this comes out of an explanatory demand, which

4:11

I think is very natural. In

4:13

the case of relations, we do think,

4:15

I think, even the ordinary view of

4:18

my opponents is that relations

4:20

must be explained. Relations are explained

4:22

in terms of the things

4:24

that are related. Relations are grounded in their

4:26

elata. And so if there's going to

4:29

be a relation, it has to be explained

4:32

by it to be grounded

4:34

in its elata. And I use

4:37

that kind of explanation or demand to show that

4:40

those kinds of explanations themselves are

4:42

not forthcoming, that relations cannot be

4:44

explained. And so because it's an

4:46

explanatory demand, for relations to be

4:49

real, they must be explained. Because

4:51

they can't be explained, it turns

4:53

out that relations are not real.

4:55

And thus, in particular, relations of

4:57

distinction between one thing and another are

5:00

not real. And so we quickly get

5:02

to the view that there are no distinctions

5:04

at all. You draw

5:06

this link between there's an

5:09

explanatory demand and the relation needs to be explained for

5:11

it to be real. Why is that the case? Can

5:13

you tell me more about what's driving that? So

5:15

I think that what's in

5:18

general is behind that is a general

5:20

version of what philosophers call the principle

5:22

of sufficient reason. For each fact, there's

5:24

a sufficient reason for that fact. There's

5:26

an explanation for that fact. So there's

5:29

this explanatory demand in general holds. But

5:31

in order to generate this argument for

5:33

the lack of distinctions, I don't need

5:36

a full blown commitment to the principle

5:38

of sufficient reason. All

5:40

that I need is just the intuitive

5:42

claim that relations

5:44

must be grounded. Relations have to be

5:47

explained. Even if facts in general don't

5:49

have to be explained, relations have to

5:51

be explained. There cannot be, as I

5:53

put it, free floating relations. Relations are

5:55

just hovering there. They

5:58

have to be grounded in something. That makes

6:00

them real if they're going to be real at all Yeah,

6:02

and can we you know make this more more concrete and

6:05

give an example? So, you know a relation might be like

6:07

the friendship between you me, you know

6:09

And what about that is

6:11

on it? So you're saying the rest of friendship is

6:13

grounded by you and me right the

6:15

relation front doesn't exist in the abstract Yes,

6:19

so there's a relation in you and

6:21

me. Okay, you exist Let's

6:23

say assume I exist let's say and

6:25

there's a relation between us That

6:28

relation or that relational fact must

6:30

be grounded in you and me

6:33

But it's also in must be

6:35

explained in that way, but it also

6:37

must be explained in terms of the

6:41

Part another relation so that

6:43

this a relation between you and me

6:45

and it's grounded in the sense in

6:47

a grounding relation To you

6:49

and it stands in a grounding relation to

6:52

me So that relation between you and me

6:54

is grounded not only in you not only

6:56

in me but also in the relation of

6:59

grounding between you and the relation and that

7:01

relation is Itself in need of

7:03

being grounded and that's going to generate another

7:05

relation and so on so the being infinite

7:08

regressive relations Once you

7:10

try to explain any given relation So

7:12

that kind of regressive relations is what's

7:14

called Bradley's regress in some version and

7:17

I have another version of that

7:19

regressive in my book That

7:21

kind of infinite regressive relations is vicious

7:23

And so it precludes it from being

7:25

the case that that any given relations

7:28

is explained And

7:30

also they there's also can

7:32

be if you don't like the vicious

7:34

regress There's also vicious circularity here whenever

7:36

we get into business of trying to

7:38

explain relations We quickly get into these

7:40

regresses or these circles that undermine any

7:42

hope of explanation, right? so

7:45

so If we

7:47

really follow this view to where it leads it's

7:49

this really radical view where distinctions and differentiation are

7:51

Unreal and all that there is is just undifferentiated

7:53

being if we apply that to language It would

7:56

mean that these work the words that

7:58

were saying right don't have differentiated distinctions That's right.

8:01

How is it that we're able to communicate right now

8:03

and understand each other intelligently? We seem to be communicating

8:05

right now, right? And that's a

8:07

wonderful thing. But on

8:10

this view that meanings

8:13

are individuated, the typical view is

8:15

that there are distinct nuggets of

8:17

meaning in language and given each

8:19

word has his own chunk of

8:21

meaning, another word has his own

8:24

meaning, etc. And these are

8:26

distinct from one another. But

8:28

if relations in general are unintelligible,

8:31

then I apply this in the case of philosophy of language.

8:34

And so individuated meanings are

8:36

unintelligible as well, right?

8:38

So this comes up in a view of

8:40

the American philosopher, great philosopher, Quine

8:42

has his view, this kind of

8:44

radical holism, radical holist

8:47

view that according to him,

8:49

there are no determinant meanings.

8:53

No word has a determinant meaning all

8:55

its own, given the holism of meaning.

8:58

And I want to take that holism even more

9:00

generally and say there's no determinant

9:02

meanings. If there's going to be meaning

9:04

at all, meaning resides in

9:07

the whole of language, not

9:09

in any discrete individual linguistic

9:11

items. So I'm not denying

9:13

that there's meaning, but meaning is not

9:15

in individual words, rather meaning is in language

9:18

as a whole. This

9:20

says I'm not denying in terms of

9:24

the topic of being that there is being,

9:26

but what I'm denying is a distinction among

9:28

individual beings, just as I'm denying

9:30

in philosophy of language, a distinction between

9:32

the meanings of individual words. In

9:35

your own words, in the book, you say philosophy is

9:37

in the business of explaining things, right? And so it

9:39

seems like language does have distinct meanings. Isn't

9:42

that something that needs to be explained in the

9:44

view? This picture of

9:46

seeing language is undifferentiated. On

9:48

that view, it's hard to understand how

9:50

it is that we're having an intelligible conversation. Right.

9:53

So two things here. One is

9:55

that I think that, again, it does seem that we're

9:57

communicating in some sense with using it in the book.

10:00

individually meaning. But that's a

10:02

verdict of common sense and relying on the

10:04

method of intuitions there. So again, I began

10:06

by saying that I'm not going to be bound

10:08

by this method of common sense or method

10:10

of intuitions because it's far too conservative for

10:12

philosophy. So you're quite right in a way to

10:14

bring up the fact, hey, it seems that we're

10:16

communicating. That's just another intuition that you have.

10:19

And we have to question that and see

10:21

where it leads. And the other

10:23

thing to mention here is that my view is

10:25

ultimately going to be a skeptical view. I'm

10:27

denying the coherence of the

10:29

concept of individually meaning. I'm denying the

10:32

coherence of the concept of distinction. So these

10:34

are ordinary concepts to which are very much

10:36

committed. But this is a skeptical view that

10:38

I'm promoting here in this vein. And I

10:40

just can answer to what extent is there

10:43

really a skepticism about philosophy or

10:45

the possibility of doing philosophy rather than a

10:48

positive metaphysical conclusion about reality, sort of oneness

10:50

or wholeness. On the one hand, you say

10:52

philosophers are obligated to try to explain everything.

10:54

But again, you're also saying that this view

10:56

type in some sense, that explanation sort of

10:59

doesn't really work in the end. So Michael,

11:01

is philosophy impossible? Well, it's

11:03

a great question. And it's

11:05

my job. I get money to behave

11:07

to be a philosopher. But I maybe

11:10

floss myself out of business here if

11:13

philosophy is not possible. And I think the

11:16

question, the skepticism here, is the skepticism about

11:18

the possibility of doing philosophy. To

11:20

the extent that philosophy depends

11:22

upon relations of distinction, which

11:25

are unintelligible, it may not be possible

11:28

to do philosophy. So that's a view that

11:30

I think we always have to keep

11:33

that possibility alive here, because it may

11:35

not be possible to do philosophy in

11:37

the terms in which we ordinarily think

11:39

it can be done, if that presupposes

11:41

distinctions, if that presupposes individuated

11:44

nuggets of meaning which are

11:46

unintelligible. Right. And so going

11:48

forward, we've been

11:51

talking a lot about the nature of

11:53

reality and metaphysics and sort of basic

11:55

ontology. But just switching gears here to

11:57

seeing how the view applies to ethics and morality.

12:00

It really seems like you

12:03

need differentiating meaning to make sense of

12:05

that. There's a difference between right

12:07

and wrong in between you and me and

12:10

in different ethical or

12:12

moral agents. So

12:14

how does the view work from reality ethics? It seems

12:16

like it just self-under money on its face. This

12:20

is a great challenge. And this is why in

12:22

the book, the Permitating

12:24

the Sandbook, I didn't directly

12:26

discuss topics of ethics because I knew that would

12:28

be the most controversial part of it. And that's

12:30

what I'm working on now to try to extend

12:32

the view into ethics. So what are the implications

12:34

for my radical monist view?

12:36

There are no distinctions for ethics. I

12:39

think the implications are

12:41

considerable. If there's a normative, non-normative

12:43

distinction, which is really what most

12:45

of moral philosophy depends on, I'm

12:48

rejecting the normative, non-normative distinction. It

12:51

doesn't mean that I'm rejecting a notion of

12:53

goodness. I'm rejecting all

12:55

kinds of notions, moral notions that

12:57

involve negativity or relations. If

12:59

there's a non-relational notion of goodness,

13:02

that can be maintained. What

13:04

cannot be maintained is the ordinary structure

13:08

of defining Kantian moral philosophy and other

13:10

forms of moral philosophy, structure of duties

13:13

and obligations and rights. All those things

13:15

ultimately don't make sense because rights and

13:17

duties and obligations are all specified in

13:19

terms of what one must not do.

13:22

And so presupposes distinctions, and that cannot

13:25

be made intelligible. But there can

13:27

be a purely positive notion of goodness.

13:30

That is what remains. And that can be what

13:35

remains of an ethical philosophy on this

13:37

view, according to which there is no

13:39

normative, non-normative distinction. Right. So

13:42

many philosophers nowadays, to make this

13:44

even more concrete, especially working in

13:47

metaphysics and analytic tradition, don't

13:50

see any implications for the researcher, for how they

13:52

live their lives. Is this a mistake that portrays

13:54

philosophy's origins in its love of wisdom? And are

13:56

there any lessons drawn from your own research that

13:58

inform how you live your This is

14:00

a question I get a lot because I

14:03

started out as a philosopher for many

14:05

years just doing things in my ivory

14:07

tower way in studying history of philosophy

14:09

and I love history of philosophy, I

14:11

still do history of philosophy, but doing

14:13

pure metaphysics with our regard to one's

14:15

life. But once I

14:18

started applying these kinds of radical,

14:20

rationalist arguments to lead to harmonious

14:22

conclusion, I saw that these

14:25

views did have applications for how one lives one's

14:28

life, especially now that I'm going into

14:30

moral implications of the view. So

14:32

yes, I think philosophy's calling and

14:34

its origins is based

14:36

on the question, how should one live one's life? And

14:39

that I think is something that these

14:41

kinds of metaphysical views, leading to undermining

14:44

of distinctions, can

14:46

have implications for how one lives one's

14:48

life because one has to embrace the

14:50

goodness, as it were, and deny negativity.

14:54

Ultimately, do you think morality is more important than metaphysics

14:56

in the end of the I think

14:58

there's no difference between morality and metaphysics. That's

15:02

what it has to be. There's no difference in

15:04

morality and metaphysics. So I think that philosophers who

15:06

tried to work just in metaphysics and not doing

15:08

moral philosophy, that's sort of just

15:10

a misguided point of view. Right.

15:12

In the end of the day, this view is you

15:15

have this nonrelational notion of being and goodness is a

15:17

part of that. So it really, we're

15:19

getting into sort of mystical territory. Do

15:22

you see yourself in that sort of mystical tradition that

15:25

begins with poor menities? I've made my piece

15:27

with that. Yes. I

15:30

used to resist the label of mysticism. But I'll

15:33

tell you a story. I gave a talk once and loved

15:36

these radical views. And someone came up to

15:38

me once and said, how does

15:40

your view differ from mysticism? And

15:42

I said, it doesn't. And I think

15:44

that I think that's not now I've embraced it. And

15:46

I think one of the things that's really interesting is

15:48

that I started out, I am

15:51

a rationalist, committed to

15:53

the principle of sufficient reason. Everything has

15:55

an explanation. But if you

15:57

take that principle of sufficient extreme, I think

15:59

you wind up in a territory

16:01

that's mystical territory. And you might think

16:03

that mysticism is incompatible with the principle

16:05

of sufficient reason. But I think it's

16:07

not. I think that if you take

16:10

this commitment to reason and rationality to

16:12

this extreme, then you're led to this

16:14

kind of mystical view where the distinctions

16:16

among things collapses, the distinction among concepts

16:18

collapses. And so this mystical view is

16:20

one that cannot be articulated in language,

16:24

as long as that language involves distinctions.

16:26

So this view cannot be articulated

16:28

in language. But it's something I got to,

16:31

this kind of non-conceptual view of

16:33

reality, as it were, through a

16:35

kind of rational argumentation. Thank

16:37

you so much. You're welcome. Thanks

16:40

for listening to Flosbee for Our Times. Don't

16:43

forget to subscribe, leave a review on your

16:45

platform of choice, and visit Ii.tv for hundreds

16:47

more podcast videos and articles from the world

16:49

that you can get. Thanks

16:52

for listening. Look

16:54

around. You can find cars like these on

16:56

AutoTrader, like that car riding your tails. Or

16:59

if you're tailgating right now, all those cars

17:01

doubling as kitchens and living rooms are on

17:03

AutoTrader too. Are you working

17:05

out and listening to this ad at the

17:08

same time? Well, multitasking pro. Cars like the

17:10

ones in the gym parking lot are for

17:12

sale on AutoTrader. New cars,

17:14

used cars, electric cars, maybe

17:16

even flying cars. OK,

17:18

no flying cars. But as soon as they get

17:20

invented, they'll be on AutoTrader. Just you

17:22

wait. AutoTrader.

Unlock more with Podchaser Pro

  • Audience Insights
  • Contact Information
  • Demographics
  • Charts
  • Sponsor History
  • and More!
Pro Features